Jeffrey Snyder is an attorney in
private practice in New York. He is working on a book called Ethical
Blindness and Moral Vanity--What the Gun Control Debate Tells Us about
the American Ethos.
Executive Summary
Ten years ago this month, a
controversial "concealed- carry" law went into effect in the
state of Florida. In a sharp break from the conventional wisdom of the
time, that law allowed adult citizens to carry concealed firearms in
public. Many people feared the law would quickly lead to disaster:
blood would literally be running in the streets. Now, 10 years later,
it is safe to say that those dire predictions were completely
unfounded. Indeed, the debate today over concealed-carry laws centers
on the extent to which such laws can actually reduce the crime
rate.
To the shock and dismay of gun
control proponents, concealed-carry reform has proven to be wildly
popular among state lawmakers. Since Florida launched its experiment
with concealed-carry in October 1987, 23 states have enacted similar
laws, with positive results.
Prior to 1987, almost every state
in America either prohibited the carrying of concealed handguns or
permitted concealed-carry under a licensing system that granted
government officials broad discretionary power over the decision to
grant a permit. The key feature of the new concealed-carry laws is
that the government must grant the permit as soon as any
citizen can satisfy objective licensing criteria.
Concealed-carry reform reaffirms
the basic idea that citizens have the right to defend themselves
against criminal attack. And since criminals can strike almost
anywhere at any time, the last thing government ought to be doing is
stripping citizens of the most effective means of defending
themselves. Carrying a handgun in public may not be for everyone, but
it is a right that government ought to respect.
Introduction
Ten years ago this month, a
controversial "concealed- carry" law went into effect in the
state of Florida. In a sharp break from the conventional wisdom of the
time, that law allowed adult citizens to carry concealed firearms in
public. Many people feared the law would quickly lead to disaster.
Blood would literally be running in the streets as citizens shot at
one another over everything from fender benders to impolite behavior.
Now, 10 years later, it is safe to say that those dire predictions
were completely unfounded. Indeed, the debate over concealed-carry
laws now centers on the extent to which those laws can actually reduce
the crime rate.
To the shock and dismay of gun
control proponents, concealed-carry reform has proven to be wildly
popular among state lawmakers. Since Florida launched its experiment
with concealed-carry in October 1987, 23 states have enacted similar
laws, with positive results. [1]
Prior to 1987, almost every state
in America either prohibited the carrying of concealed handguns or
permitted concealed-carry under a licensing system that granted
government officials broad discretionary power over the decision to
grant a permit. The key feature of the new concealed-carry laws is
that the issuing authority--usually a sheriff or the chief of police--must
grant the permit as soon as a citizen can satisfy specific and
objective licensing criteria. It is for that reason that those reforms
are often referred to as "shall-issue" concealed-carry laws.
After a brief review of the history
of concealed-carry laws and handgun licensing, this study will compare
and contrast the discretionary permitting system with the new,
"shall-issue" licensing regime. The study will then examine
and refute the most common objections that have been lodged against
the right of an adult citizen to carry a handgun in public. It is the
thesis of this study that citizens have the right to defend themselves
against criminal attack-–and that the last thing government ought to
be doing is stripping its citizens of the most effective means by
which they can defend themselves. Carrying a handgun in public may not
be for everyone, but it is a right that government ought to respect.
A Brief History of Firearms
Regulation
In order to get some perspective on
the concealed-carry debate, it will be useful to review the history of
firearms regulation in the United States. Three historical
observations are particularly relevant for the purposes of this study.
First, firearms regulation has traditionally been a matter of state
law. Second, while some states have had laws prohibiting the
concealed-carry of weapons since the Civil War, it was, at the time
those prohibitions were enacted, perfectly legal to carry a gun openly
in public. In fact, it is still legal today, if not socially
acceptable, to carry a gun openly in public in some states. Third,
during the 20th century, most states adhered to a liberal policy
concerning the acquisition or ownership of firearms but adopted
strict rules concerning the carrying of concealed weapons in
public.
The "Ignoble Act"
of Carrying Concealed Weapons
There appears to have been no
general statutory restrictions on the ability of citizens to carry
arms in the American colonies (excluding, of course, the attempts of
the English to disarm the colonists immediately preceding the American
Revolution). Nor can one find any examples of general statutory
restrictions of, or prohibitions against, the carrying of arms, either
openly or concealed, in the early American states. That absence of
restrictions corresponds perfectly to the historical fact that our
forebears understood that they had an individual right to possess and
carry arms for defense, subject to the common law restriction, noted
by Sir William Blackstone, that one could not carry such arms as were
apt to terrify the people or make an affray of the peace.
Restrictions on the concealed-carry
of weapons first appeared in the South in the years preceding the
Civil War; Kentucky's were the first in 1813. Few persons had
revolvers in those days, and the most feared of concealed weapons was
the Bowie knife, not the handgun. [2] By
1850 most Southern states, and Indiana, had prohibited the
concealed-carry of weapons, including firearms.
Clayton Cramer, who has made an
extensive historical review of case law relating to the right to keep
and bear arms under the Second Amendment and state constitutional
guarantees, notes that the common characteristic of the states
adopting those laws was slavery. The sole exception, Indiana, also
serves to prove the point, because it was largely settled by
Southerners with strong Southern sympathies. The 1850 Indiana
constitution, Cramer points out, prohibited both slavery and free
blacks from entering the state. Cramer suggests that the most likely
explanation for concealed-carry laws is, therefore, to be found in the
problem of race. [3]
Law professors Robert Cottrol and
Raymond Diamond suggest that the desire to control blacks was the
principal, or at least a significant, reason for the Southern gun
control laws in the years preceding the Civil War. [4]
While that may explain the laws that licensed blacks to carry or own
guns or prohibited them from carrying or owning arms, it does not
explain why the Southern states took the additional step of
restricting whites from carrying arms concealed. The answer, according
to Cramer, may lie in the abolition movement.
The problem of mob violence
directed against abolitionists was sufficiently widespread during
the 1830s, when the concealed weapons laws became increasingly
common in the South, that President Martin Van Buren's Inaugural
Address, delivered in March of 1837, addressed the problem twice.
In the South, where slaveholders
were overwhelmingly in control, laws to protect attacking mobs from
the unfair advantage of abolitionists carrying concealed weapons
would not be surprising. . . . In Northern states, where
slaveholders had little direct influence on state governments, the
need to keep abolitionists in fear might have been less obvious. . .
.
The most obvious connection to
prohibition of concealed carry of arms in the South is that most of
these laws were adopted in the years immediately following Nat
Turner's 1831 rebellion. While free blacks were banned from carrying
weapons (openly or concealed) in statutes different from those that
banned concealed carry, the curious grouping in geography and time
of these laws suggests that fear of slave revolt, or of armed
abolitionists, or both, provoked these laws. A detailed history of
each state's concealed weapons statutes is . . . necessary to
resolve the question of why these laws appeared almost exclusively
in slave states during the antebellum period. [5]
While fear of slave revolts or
armed abolitionists may have provided the underlying motivation for
those laws, it was not, for obvious reasons, the stated justification
for them. The Southern states that outlawed concealed-carry justified
such laws, in theory, as a means of restricting the conduct of
criminals, while leaving the law-abiding alone, free to carry
honestly. In the words of the Louisiana Supreme Court, laws
prohibiting the concealed-carry of weapons
became absolutely necessary to
counteract a vicious state of society, growing out of the habit of
carrying concealed weapons, and to prevent bloodshed and
assassinations committed upon unsuspecting persons. [Such laws]
interfered with no man's right to carry arms . . . "in full
open view," which places men upon an equality. This
[open-carry] is the right guaranteed by the Constitution of the
United States, and which is calculated to incite men to manly and
noble defense of themselves, if necessary, and of their country,
without any tendency to secret advantages and unmanly assassination.
[6]
Thus, it is important to understand
the background against which those prohibitions were upheld by the
courts. The prohibition (as opposed to the licensing) of
concealed-carry developed in states that generally did not restrict
the open-carry of firearms, at least by whites. (Numerous Southern
states outlawed either ownership or carrying of firearms by slaves and
freed black men who, it was feared, would lead slave revolts.) Indeed,
in some states it is still legal to carry firearms openly in public.
Unlicensed open-carry is still the law in Virginia, Nevada, and Maine,
for example.
At the time the restrictions were
enacted, then, people were generally free to carry firearms openly.
Honest men engaged in lawful behavior had no reason to take pains to
hide their weapons, for weapons were a part of everyday life. In a
society in which open-carry was the norm, the natural presumption was
that one was unarmed if his weapon was not in plain sight. In that
context, concealment was regarded as an act of deception, an ignoble
act designed to gain unfair or surprise advantage over others.
Open-carry placed men in a position of equality with respect to one
another by giving all fair warning whether any was armed. Since those
who carried concealed weapons sought a deadly, unfair advantage,
criminal or malicious intent was effectively presumed.
States Assert Control over
the Ownership of Handguns
Licensing systems regulating the
concealed-carry of firearms appear to have developed in the Northeast
and were put in place in most states in the years 1901-40. In 1911 New
York enacted the Sullivan Law, which was to become the model for
restricting the ownership and carrying of handguns. [7]
The law outlawed handgun ownership without a police permit and
was modeled after European firearms laws that were considered to be
successful in dealing with political dissidents, anarchists, and labor
agitators.
By 1934 Sullivan-type permit
requirements for buying a handgun had been adopted by Arkansas,
Michigan, Missouri, New Jersey, North Carolina, Hawaii, and Oregon. [8]
National and local business associations were among the most vocal
lobbyists in support of the Sullivan Law, and laws in other states
modeled on it, emphasizing the increasing incidence of armed robbery.
At the time, armed robbery was not merely an issue of public safety;
the crime had distinct political connotations:
Armed robbery was associated in
the public mind with foreign immigrants, not just because they were
considered naturally lazy and inclined to violent acquisitiveness,
but because armed robbery was a recognized tactic of the
"foreign-born anarchists." In America from at least the
turn of the century, and in Europe from the 1870s on,
revolutionaries used bank and commercial robberies as a means of
gathering funds to finance their underground activities. The
businessmen's association could point out that Sacco and Vanzetti
were originally apprehended for violation of Massachusetts' new
handgun law, and that they were executed for murder committed in the
course of several armed robberies of which they were convicted. [9]
The Sullivan Law introduced two
criteria that were to become widely adopted, with some variation, in
most states throughout the 1920s and early 1930s. Handguns could not
be acquired without a permit issued only to persons who had both
"good moral character" and "good cause" to carry a
handgun. That approach apparently was readily appealing to legislators
in other states precisely because it seemed such a well-devised means
of ensuring that the "wrong" sort of people did not obtain
firearms, and could not carry them. The statute was not on its face
discriminatory on grounds of race, religion, national origin, or
political beliefs. Instead, broad, uncircumscribed discretion granted
in self-validating yet empty licensing criteria ("good moral
character," "good cause") enabled the police or other
licensing authorities to target specific groups deemed the source of
violent crime and political conflict: Italians, Jews, or the
foreign-born (misperceived as naturally possessing criminal
propensities or having little attachment to traditional American
institutions and values), African-Americans, labor agitators, and
those suspected of "anarcho-syndicalism" by virtue of their
political beliefs, associational activities, or country of origin.
While Northern states may have
favored the discretionary licensing laws as a means of ensuring that
Italians, Jews, labor agitators, or others with radical political
beliefs did not obtain arms, Southern states favored such laws because
the broad discretion permitted maneuvering room to deny permits to
African-Americans. [10] The racist
motivation for, and racist application of, such laws was noted in a
1941 court case involving Florida's old discretionary licensing
system: "The statute was never intended to be applied to the
white population and in practice has never been so applied. . . .
[The] Act was passed for the purpose of disarming the negro laborers
and to thereby reduce the [number of] unlawful homicides . . . and to
give the white citizens in sparsely settled areas a better feeling of
security. . . . There has never been, within my knowledge, any effort
to enforce the provisions of this statute as to white people, because
it has been generally conceded to be in contravention of the
Constitution and non-enforceable if contested. [11]
The Great Compromise: Liberal
Rules on Gun Ownership, Strict Rules on Carrying Guns in Public
Faced with the threat of a growing
number of states adopting Sullivan Law type prohibitions on the
acquisition (and thus ownership) of handguns without police permits,
the National Rifle Association endorsed and supported a compromise
program to protect gun ownership while reducing crime associated with
the carrying of handguns--the Uniform Firearms Act, also known as the
Uniform Revolver Act.
The origin of the Uniform Revolver
Act is somewhat unclear. Some sources report that the model act was
drafted by a former president of the NRA, Karl T. Frederick, or by the
NRA itself, and endorsed by the National Conference of Commissioners
on Uniform State Laws in 1925. [12] Another
source indicates "that it was the product of a committee
appointed by the National Conference of Commissioners on Uniform State
Laws in 1923, at the urging of the United States Revolver
Association," and adopted in final form in 1930. [13]
Regardless, the model act avoided the Sullivan Law's requirement of a
police permit to acquire a handgun but essentially adopted its
criteria for purposes of licensing the carrying of handguns.
Concealed-carry without a license
was made illegal (usually a misdemeanor). The licensing
authority--typically the sheriff, the chief of police, or a local
court--was granted authority to issue permits to persons who both had
"good moral character" and satisfied some needs-based
requirement, such as having "good cause," or demonstrating a
"need" to carry a handgun. The law was adopted in 1923 by
California, North Dakota, and New Hampshire. By 1940 it had been
adopted by virtually every state, including several that had
previously adopted (but now repealed) Sullivan-type permit systems. [14]
Essentially, then, it is the system established by the Uniform
Revolver Act, with its twin requirements of demonstrating good
character and some need to carry arms, that has been the focus of the
recent shall-issue carry reforms, and it is that system that continues
in the 15 states that still have discretionary licensing systems in
place.
The point of this brief historical
review is not to argue that the discretionary licensing system
ultimately created by the Uniform Revolver Act is inherently racist,
discriminatory on the basis of national origin, anti-Semitic,
xenophobic, or illiberal because formed during the social conflicts of
the labor movement, anarcho-syndicalism, massive immigration from
Central and Eastern Europe, and racial strife. It is not. The point is
that the twin criteria, "good moral character" and
"need" or "good cause," were favored precisely
because they were vague enough to ensure that only the
"right" sort of people could carry arms, however conceived
from age to age, or region to region. While self-justifying and
apparently even-handed on the surface, the criteria are so broad,
undefined, and devoid of any objective standards that they pose no
obstacle to granting or withholding licenses in a highly
discriminatory, prejudicial, arbitrary, or political manner. The
history of the laws regulating the carrying of firearms also should
alert us to the manner in which gun control laws embody the political
and social fears of their time and the often unconscious class and
social presumptions underlying those laws, easily justified and made
antiseptic when discussed only in terms of the abstract concern for
"public safety." [15]
The Arbitrary Nature of
Discretionary Licensing
The most serious problem with
discretionary licensing systems is the broad discretionary power that
is wielded by government officials. Historically, as discussed above,
the problems have been discriminatory application of those laws based
on race, national origin, or political activities. The contemporary
problems with those laws, however, tend to be (a) discrimination based
on population density; (b) class discrimination; (c) arbitrary,
inconsistent, and irrational application of the law; and (d)
favoritism or corruption.
The operative language of the
statutes in the jurisdictions that continue to use discretionary
systems is essentially a variant of the Uniform Revolver Act
requirements of "good moral character" and a
"need" or "good cause." The arbitrary nature of
the discretion granted to licensing authorities is apparent from the
language of the state laws that maintain those systems. Here are a few
examples:
· California:
The licensing authority "may issue" a permit "upon
proof that the applicant is of good moral character," and that
"good cause" exists. [16]
· Colorado:
The licensing authority "may issue" a permit following a
background check to determine "if the applicant would be a
danger to others or to himself or herself." [17]
· New
York: The licensing authority "shall issue" a permit if
the applicant is of "good moral character," "no good
cause exists for the denial of the license," and "proper
cause" exists for the issuance of the license. [18]
· North
Dakota: The licensing authority "shall issue" a permit if
the applicant "has the written approval . . . from the sheriff
of the applicant's county and, if the city has one, the chief of
police or a designee of the city." [19]
· Rhode
Island: The licensing authority "shall issue" a permit if
the applicant "has good reason to fear injury to his or her
person or property, or has any other proper reason for
carrying," and is a "suitable person" to be licensed.
[20]
Before examining the evidence of
how discretionary licensing systems have actually operated, it will be
useful to note some of the characteristics of those laws that so
readily lend themselves to abuse. First, although some of the statutes
provide that the licensing authority "shall issue" the
permit, it is likely to make little practical difference in the
application of the law because the licensing criteria are sufficiently
undefined or vague to provide ample room to deny issuance of a permit.
Statutes that provide that the licensing authority "may"
issue permits to appropriate persons nevertheless provide additional,
undefined discretion by suggesting that the criteria listed in the
licensing statute are by no means exhaustive or determinative--other
reasons, unstated, may be found by the licensor to deny the permit.
Second, the applicant must bear the
burden of proving to the licensing authority's satisfaction that he
has the requisite "moral character" and "justifiable
need" or other "proper cause" to carry a firearm. As a
practical matter, therefore, if the application for a permit is
denied, even arbitrarily, the applicant's only remedy is to appeal to
the courts for review. Such a procedure imposes significant cost and
time burdens on the applicant for a permit to carry
firearms--effectively precluding the acquisition of permits by the
poor, by elderly pensioners, and by anyone else whose discretionary
income does not permit a gamble on the court system.
Third, the fact that the statutes
limit permits to persons who have "good reason to fear
injury," "justifiable need," "proper cause,"
or similar qualifications gives short shrift to the general risk that
each person faces simply by living in a society where predatory
criminals roam about freely. Implicit in the needs-based language of
discretionary statutes is the notion that the privilege of carrying
arms is a function of the risk of criminal victimization: that people
who, because of their circumstance, face an unusually high risk of
criminal victimization and are in some sense "natural"
targets of criminal assault or special targets of opportunity have a
justifiable "need" to carry arms; the rest of the populace,
who face only an "ordinary" risk, is not justified in
wanting to carry arms to defend itself. Not only is there no reason to
believe that those who face an unusual risk of criminal victimization
are inherently more trustworthy or competent with a firearm than those
who do not, but the implicit suggestion that some lives--because of
wealth, fame, unique job requirements, or the preferences of
criminals--are somehow more worth protecting than others is morally
repugnant and indefensible.
In essence, "need"-based
or "cause"-based licensing systems imply that one's right to
life is a function of one's risk of criminal victimization. Those for
whom the risk is greatest have a right to life (i.e., to preserve that
life by using a gun to defend one's self against unlawful deadly
force). Those whose risk is low or ordinary are handicapped by the
law--stripped of the right of self-defense. Despite the inherent,
bizarre nature of the notion that one's right to life fades in and out
of existence depending on fluctuations in the rate of violent crime or
the preferences of criminals, one nevertheless hears the idea
expressed in prestigious circles. Columnist Charles Krauthammer, for
example, has observed that Americans would not be willing to accept
strict gun control, including the banning of handguns, until the
government could demonstrate that it could keep crime at a low level. [21]
Krauthammer's claim implies that people will or should give up the
right to defend their lives (a right, incidentally, that Hobbes,
Locke, and the Founders described as "inalienable" and that
the Declaration of Independence described as a right governments were
instituted to secure) just as soon as government demonstrates its
success at keeping the overall risk of criminal victimization low.
A review of how discretionary
licensing systems have in fact been administered confounds any attempt
to find a coherent or consistent application of the laws. In fact, one
of the most respected American legal encyclopedias, American Law
Reports, states simply that the results of cases that have
specifically addressed the issue of who is entitled to carry firearms
"are not necessarily reconcilable, differing results having been
reached as to applications offering similar evidence or allegations
concerning the kinds of dangers to which the applicants claimed they
had been subjected, and from which they allegedly required means of
personal protection." [22] In other
words, the laws, embodying similar concepts, are applied as those in
charge of administering and interpreting them see fit on a
case-by-case basis.
In Denver, Police Chief Ari Zavaras
granted only 45 permits in a city of one-half million people. [23]
The detective who administered Zavaras's permit program explained that
only applicants with a "true and compelling need" could be
granted permits. "Just because you fear for your life is not a
compelling reason to have a permit," he said. [24]
Among those denied a permit was Denver talk-show host Alan Berg, who
had received death threats from, and was later killed by, white
supremacists.
From 1984 to 1992 the City of Los
Angeles refused to issue a single permit. In a city of 3.5 million
people, over a period of nine years, not one applicant was found to
have both "good moral character" and "good cause"
to carry a handgun for protection. [25] As
of 1992 only about 400 concealed-carry permits were issued to Los
Angeles County's population of 8.86 million (0.005 percent). As of
1994, prior to Virginia's adoption of a shall-issue licensing system,
only 10 persons of Fairfax County's population of over 850,000 (0.001
percent) had permits. [26] By comparison,
as of 1994 two other states with discretionary licensing systems,
Connecticut, with a population of about 3.28 million, and Indiana,
with a population of about 5.54 million, had approximately 116,000 and
221,000 outstanding permits to carry firearms, respectively (3.54
percent and 3.99 percent, respectively).
To provide further perspective,
contrast those numbers with the numbers in two states that had
shall-issue licensing statutes. In 1992 Pennsylvania, with a
population of about 12 million, had approximately 362,000 outstanding
permits to carry firearms (3.02 percent), and Washington, with a
population of about 4.86 million, had approximately 242,000
outstanding permits to carry firearms (4.98 percent). The Los Angeles
City homicide rate around that time was approximately twice as high as
that of Indianapolis and three times as high as that of Pittsburgh or
Seattle. [27] The most dangerous city
issued the fewest permits per capita.
It is hard to reconcile those
wildly contrasting results with any uniform principle rationally
related to (a) ensuring that law-abiding citizens may carry in public
a means with which to protect themselves from deadly criminal force
while (b) providing reasonable assurance to the public at large that
those who do so may be reasonably expected to act responsibly, which
one would expect ought to be the goal of a rational licensing system.
To the extent that it is possible
to find any rule approximately describing those results, it is that
permits are generally freely issued to law-abiding citizens in rural
areas or areas of relatively low population density, while they are
denied as a matter of course to persons who inhabit cities and
metropolitan suburbs. There is a plausible sociological explanation
for this state of affairs. Guns are not feared objects in rural areas.
Crime is lower, guns are more a part of everyday life and have a
"positive image," being associated predominantly with their
sporting and recreational use. Everybody knows everybody, everybody
knows many people who have guns, and most people do not think that
their friends, neighbors, and relatives are likely to go on shooting
sprees or shoot others in a moment of anger. By contrast, in cities,
guns are associated in the popular mind mostly with criminal violence
and are therefore evil objects to be despised. No one knows anyone, no
one trusts anyone, and everyone knows that everyone else is a
potential powderkeg waiting to explode. It is perhaps not surprising
that if we enact a law that grants authority to issue permits to carry
firearms on a discretionary basis, we will obtain results that mirror
the different sociological perceptions of those who live in urban and
rural areas, rural down-homeness and urban paranoia. Whether such
perceptions serve well as a basis for providing equal protection of
the law is another matter entirely.
Within metropolitan areas, the
issuance of permits under discretionary systems depends on factors
unrelated to any simple determination of whether the applicant can be
reasonably expected to act responsibly. The list of permit holders in
New York City, for example, strongly suggests that the Sullivan Law
has been applied on the basis of wealth, celebrity status, political
influence, and favoritism. Licensees have included and include such
luminaries as Eleanor Roosevelt, Lyman Bloomingdale, Henry Cabot
Lodge, Nelson Rockefeller, Laurence Rockefeller, Mayor John Lindsay, New
York Times publisher Arthur Ochs Sulzberger, William F. Buckley
Jr., Donald Trump, Leland DuPont, publisher Michael Korda, Arthur
Godfrey, Sammy Davis Jr., Robert Goulet, Sid Caesar, Bill Cosby, Joan
Rivers, and Howard Stern. Other licensees have included several major
slumlords, a Teamsters Union boss who was a defendant in a major
racketeering suit, and a restaurateur with ties to organized crime. [28]
Meanwhile, taxi drivers, who face a high risk of robbery, "are
denied gun permits because they carry less than $2,000 in cash," [29]
and city courts have ruled that ordinary citizens and store owners may
not receive permits to carry firearms because they have no greater
need for protection than does anyone else in the city.
A federal district court in
California upheld similar class-based discrimination in Los Angeles
County's policy of issuing permits to carry firearms almost entirely
to retired police officers and celebrities, "because famous
persons and public figures are often subjected to threats of bodily
harm." [30] Thus, if you are famous
enough to attract death threats, you may carry an effective means with
which to defend your life. If you are not famous and the criminals do
not extend the courtesy of first warning you that you may be
victimized but simply surprise you one day with robbery, rape, or
attempted murder, then you do not deserve the right to protect
yourself with a handgun. Special treatment for special people.
There is also evidence to suggest
that the discretionary systems invite favoritism and possibly
corruption. On January 22, 1996, the New York City Police Department
of Internal Affairs removed Deputy Inspector Henry Krantz, a 30-year
veteran, from the pistol licensing division, removed licensing
records, and took over administration of the office because he
allegedly favored certain applicants and afforded preferential
treatment in the grant of licenses and because he allegedly wrongfully
directed other cops to grant favors. [31]
The point of these comparisons and
observations is that the discretionary licensing systems invite and
produce discrimination on grounds of class, race, religion, country of
origin, fame, wealth, or political influence in a manner that has no
rational correlation with risk of criminal victimization (assuming
discrimination on the basis of victimization risk were proper or moral
to begin with) or with trustworthiness or competence with a firearm.
Such systems invite, and in fact produce, wholly inconsistent,
arbitrary, and irrational results. Some opponents of shall-issue
licensing laws criticize the inadequacy of training requirements in
the shall-issue laws, but nothing in the discretionary systems ensures
that celebrities or other permit holders will get any firearms
training.
Opponents of shall-issue licensing
laws often describe them as reforms that "liberalize" the
laws permitting the carrying of arms, as if we were loosening the
standards. In fact, the discretionary standards are not standards, for
they do not produce standard results. As the preceding comparison of
the number of permits issued in Connecticut and Indiana
(discretionary-issuance states) with the number issued in Pennsylvania
(a shall-issue state) indicates, there is nothing inherent in the
discretionary licensing systems that guarantees that fewer permits
will be issued per capita than under shall-issue systems (3.54 percent
in Connecticut, 3.99 percent in Indiana, and 3.02 percent in
Pennsylvania). [32] If you provide no
defined rule to guide conduct, you cannot expect to obtain results
that conform to any particular standard. [33]
In short, the results appear to depend entirely on the subjective
interpretations and whims of those administering the law. Regardless
of one's opinion about whether law-abiding citizens should be
permitted to carry arms, the discretionary licensing systems deserve
to be repealed and replaced. They are intolerably arbitrary.
The Objective Nature of
Shall-Issue Licensing
Critics of shall-issue licensing
laws decry the fact that "anyone" or "everyone"
can carry a gun. That is nothing but hyperbolic rhetoric. While the
licensing criteria generally permit nearly all law-abiding adults to
carry guns, they manifestly do not include just "anyone" or
"everyone." In general, in the 25 states that have enacted
shall-issue licensing systems, an applicant will be issued a permit to
carry a concealed weapon if he or she
·
is at least 21 years of age;
·
is a resident of the state;
·
provides fingerprints and submits to a criminal and mental health
background check;
·
has not been convicted of a felony or any crime punishable by
imprisonment for more than one year;
·
is not a fugitive from justice;
·
is not an illegal alien;
·
is not an unlawful user of or addicted to any controlled substance;
·
has not been adjudicated mentally incompetent or been committed to a
mental institution;
·
has not been dishonorably discharged from the armed services;
·
is not subject to a restraining or protection order;
·
has not been convicted of a misdemeanor crime of domestic violence;
· is
not awaiting trial for, and does not have any charges pending for, a
crime punishable by more than one year imprisonment;
· has
completed a firearms safety or training course; and
· pays
a licensing fee.
The term of the license varies from
two to five years, and most states (60 percent) have adopted a term of
four years. Fees to acquire a permit, exclusive of training course
costs and fingerprint processing fees (which several states assess
separately), vary from a minimum of $6 (South Dakota) to $140 (Texas),
with the majority of states charging under $100. Variations in
licensing criteria exist from state to state, and some states impose
more rigorous requirements than others. The requirements listed above
are generally the minimum requirements present in most of the
shall-issue licensing systems now in place. Table 1 shows some of the
specific criteria for each state.
Table 1
Variation in Certain Licensing Criteria
State |
Avail.
to
Residents/
Nonresidents |
Age |
Fingerprints
&
Background Ck. |
Firearms
Training |
Fee($) |
Term
(yrs) |
Alaska |
R |
21 |
F & B |
yes |
125 |
5 |
Arizona |
R |
21 |
F & B |
yes |
NS |
4 |
Arkansas |
R |
21 |
F & B |
yes |
100+F |
4 |
Florida |
R & NR |
21 |
F & B |
yes |
85+F |
3 |
Georgia |
R |
21 |
F & B |
no |
20 |
5 |
Idaho |
R & NR |
21 |
F & B |
no |
20+F |
4 |
Louisiana |
R |
21 |
F & B |
yes |
100 |
4 |
Maine |
R & NR |
18 |
B |
yes |
35 |
4 |
Mississippi |
R |
21 |
F & B |
no |
100+F |
4 |
Montana |
R |
18 |
F & B |
yes |
55 |
4 |
Nevada |
R |
21 |
F & B |
yes |
60+F |
5 |
N. Hampshire |
R & NR |
NS |
no |
no |
10 |
4 |
N. Carolina |
R |
21 |
F & B |
yes |
NS |
4 |
Oklahoma |
R |
23 |
F & B |
yes |
100+F |
4 |
Oregon |
R |
21 |
F & B |
yes |
65 |
4 |
Pennsylvania |
R & NR |
21 |
B |
no |
19 |
5 |
S. Carolina |
R |
21 |
F & B |
yes |
55 |
4 |
S. Dakota |
R & NR |
18 |
no |
no |
6 |
4 |
Tennessee |
R |
18 |
F & B |
yes |
100 |
4 |
Texas |
R |
21 |
F & B |
yes |
140 |
4 |
Utah |
R & NR |
21 |
F & B |
yes |
35 |
2 |
Virginia |
R |
21 |
B |
yes |
40 |
2 |
Washington |
R & NR |
21 |
F & B |
no |
36+F |
5 |
W. Virginia |
R |
18 |
F & B |
yes |
75 |
5 |
Wyoming |
R |
21 |
F & B |
yes |
50+F |
5 |
Note: NS means that this item is not specified in the statute.
F indicates that the cost of fingerprint processing or Federal Bureau
of Investigation fingerprint check is charged separately. |
There are two important differences between the discretionary
licensing system and the shall-issue licensing system. First, under
the shall-issue system, the legal presumption is on the side of the
individual citizen. That is, the government must come forward with a
reason why a citizen should not be allowed to carry a concealed
weapon. Under discretionary licensing, the legal presumption is on the
side of the government. That is, the citizen has to come forward with
a reason why he should be permitted to carry a concealed weapon. The
second difference is that, whereas the eligibility requirements under
discretionary licensing are vague and undefined, the eligibility
criteria under a shall-issue system are objectively verifiable, as
discussed below.
Disqualifications for
Criminal Conduct
Most states expressly provide that
anyone who is ineligible to possess a handgun under federal or state
law may not obtain a permit. Federal law outlaws possession by anyone
(a) who has been convicted of a crime punishable by imprisonment for a
term exceeding one year, (b) who is a fugitive from justice, (c) who
is an unlawful user of or addicted to any controlled substance, (d)
who has been adjudicated a "mental defective" or been
committed to a mental institution, (e) who is an illegal alien, (f)
who was dishonorably discharged from the armed services, (g) who has
renounced his U.S. citizenship, (h) who is subject to certain types of
restraining orders, or (i) who has been convicted of a misdemeanor
crime of domestic violence. [34]
Actually, it makes little
difference whether the licensing statute refers to or restates those
disqualifications. So long as the state requires a criminal background
check, the check will disclose whether the applicant who desires to
carry a firearm is permitted to possess a firearm under federal or
state law. If not, obviously no permit may issue, and the applicant's
possession of a weapon would be in violation of federal or state law.
Further, since permit holders are registered, that is, the application
information is maintained in the state's criminal records, the data
provide a ready means of identifying and confiscating the weapons of
permit holders who commit a crime postissuance or otherwise become
disqualified (e.g., by drug use or mental illness). Critics of laws
liberalizing the ability of citizens to carry firearms in public often
ignore the fact that the new licensing statutes provide an ongoing way
of policing compliance with federal and state laws regarding firearm
ownership.
Conversely, the registration aspect
of those laws, with its attendant specter of the possibility of
confiscation, may be one of the reasons why only a fraction of gun
owners have applied for permits. The unlicensed carrying of a
concealed handgun is generally a misdemeanor, not a felony. Some gun
owners may prefer to take their chances with unlicensed carrying of a
concealed firearm, presuming that so long as they are engaged in
lawful activity, they may rely on their Fourth Amendment rights
against unreasonable searches and seizures to avoid detection by the
police.
Many states go beyond the criteria
relating to ineligibility to own or possess a firearm. Typically, they
do so in three ways. First, they provide either that permits may not
be issued, or that the licensing authority has the discretion to deny
the issuance of permits, to persons who have committed one or more
crimes of violence constituting a misdemeanor within a certain time
period, such as three years, prior to the date of the application.
Second, because the minimum age is
generally 21, they provide disqualifications for adjudications of
juvenile delinquency if the crime would have been a felony if
committed by an adult, or if the crime was one of violence, would have
been a misdemeanor and was committed within a certain period before
the application was made.
Finally, in apparent recognition of
the many means of sentencing criminals in a system that has
insufficient resources to convict and jail every guilty person, the
licensing statutes disqualify persons who have had adjudication of
guilt withheld or imposition of sentence deferred or suspended on any
felony unless a certain specified time, such as three years, has
elapsed since the probation period or other conditions set by the
court have been fulfilled.
Only one state, Texas, uses the
licensing occasion to impose requirements not related to matters
probative of whether the applicant may pose a danger to others if
permitted to carry his weapon. Texas provides that the license may not
be granted if the applicant is delinquent with child support payments,
taxes, or has defaulted on a student loan. Whether other states will
decide to use permits as a tool for social engineering remains to be
seen.
Disqualifications for Mental
Incapacity
Nearly all states that have enacted
shall-issue licensing laws have provided that an adjudication of
mental incompetency, mental deficiency, or mental illness disqualifies
the applicant for a permit. That requirement is in accord with federal
law relating to eligibility to own firearms. Many, if not most, state
statutes, however, also provide that voluntary or involuntary
commitment to a mental health institution within a specified time
period preceding the date of application, such as three or five years,
also disqualifies the applicant. [35] At
least one state, Oklahoma, makes attempted suicide grounds for denial.
Texas goes furthest by providing that a prior diagnosis by a
qualified, licensed physician of depression, manic depression, or
posttraumatic stress syndrome disqualifies the applicant unless the
applicant can present a certificate from a licensed physician
attesting that he no longer suffers from that disability and is not on
medication for that disability.
Several of the licensing laws
specifically provide that the application constitutes a waiver of
confidentiality or privacy laws granting the licensing authority
access to mental health records at public and, in some cases, private
health and drug treatment institutions. The waiver is not
circumscribed in purpose or time and is seemingly permanent. The
apparently permanent grant to the police of roving access to personal
health records may be another reason why many individuals do not
choose to apply for permits.
Disqualifications Relating to
Alcohol and Drugs
Nearly all states provide that use
of marijuana, narcotic drugs, or controlled substances disqualifies
the applicant for a permit to carry a concealed weapon. Again, that
minimum is essentially provided by federal law. Many, if not most,
states go beyond the minimum in various ways. Generally, the laws will
provide one or more of the following: (a) that being committed to an
alcohol or drug treatment facility within a specified time period
preceding the date of the application disqualifies the applicant; (b)
that being convicted of a misdemeanor involving marijuana or other
drugs within a specified time period (for example, five years) before
the date of application disqualifies the applicant; or (c) that being
convicted of one or more driving-under-the-influence offenses within a
specified time period (for example, five years) preceding the date of
application disqualifies the applicant. [36]
A few states, such as Oregon and South Carolina, have no express
disqualifications for alcohol or drug use. Since those states run
background checks, however, they automatically give effect to the
minimum federal restrictions.
Training Requirements
Eighteen of the 25 states (72
percent) that have enacted shall-issue licensing laws require the
applicant to have taken some training course. With the sole exception
of New Hampshire, every state that has enacted a shall-issue licensing
system since 1991 has required some sort of training. The statutory
requirements are generally phrased in terms of the applicant's being
required to demonstrate "competence,"
"familiarity" or "proficiency" with a handgun by
providing the government with a certificate from a qualified or
licensed firearms trainer or an approved training course. The statutes
generally specify the types of courses that are approved so that the
training course requirements are not left entirely to the discretion
of the police. While some licensing laws require or authorize the
issuing authority to offer training courses, all states with training
requirements permit the requirement to be satisfied by privately
offered courses.
In general, the training course
specifications fall into two categories: some states simply specify
the acceptable types of courses, without specifying content
requirements, and other states specify course content requirements.
States that simply specify course type generally permit the training
requirement to be satisfied by several or all of the following:
·
completion of a hunter education or hunter safety course;
· completion
of any NRA firearms safety or training course, including its
personal protection program;
·
completion of any firearms safety or training course or class
available to the general public offered by law enforcement, junior
college, private or public institution, organization, or other
firearms training school, using instructors certified by the
National Rifle Association, by the licensing authority or by other
specified divisions of the state; or
·
firearms training received in the armed services.
The purpose of the training
requirement, presumably, is to provide reasonable assurance to society
at large that permit holders know how to safely handle a firearm,
possess minimum shooting proficiency, and are familiar with the
state's laws relating to the justifiable use of lethal force in
self-defense, much as a driver's license assures society that those
driving on public roads have a minimum skill in handling their
vehicles and a minimum knowledge of traffic rules and regulations.
Judging by that standard, [37] there are
three potential problems with the training requirements that specify
only course type, without regard to content:
·
There is no specified requirement that the applicant actually
demonstrate safe handling of handguns and shooting proficiency at a
firing range (as distinguished from demonstrating an understanding
of the principles of such behavior, by written test, for example).
·
No objective specification of minimum shooting proficiency is
provided.
·
There is no specified requirement that instruction be given in the
state's law regarding the justifiable (or excusable) use of lethal
force in self-defense.
Note that those omissions are only
a potential problem because some courses might actually address
those issues, depending on the instructor. Since the requirements are
not specified in the law, however, there is no uniform standard that
the public can look to for assurance that permit holders possess
certain minimum skills and knowledge.
For example, firearms training in
the military would not necessarily involve education in a state's laws
relating to the justifiable use of lethal force, although it would
obviously entail training in the safe handling of weapons and range
training. Similarly, hunter education courses are generally taken by
boys and girls in their midteens in order to obtain a hunting license.
Since most hunting is done with rifles or shotguns, such training will
involve knowledge of the safe handling of loaded weapons, but it will
not involve instruction in a state's self-defense laws. Nor do such
programs necessarily involve range time, even with a rifle or shotgun.
Arguably, therefore, states that
permit hunter education courses and military training to satisfy the
training requirement have the weakest training standards. On the other
hand, people who have been hunting for a number of years or who have
served in the military arguably have more experience safely carrying
loaded weapons and firing their weapons under some stress or pressure
(even when hunting, for example, the shot must be fired quickly but
accurately, for the deer, rabbit, or whatever will soon be gone or
move behind obstructions). The selection of this standard is not,
therefore, per se irrational; its principal weakness is the lack of
education in the state's laws regarding the use of lethal force in
self-defense.
Five states, namely, Alaska,
Arizona, Oklahoma, Texas, and Utah, specify content requirements for
training courses. Each of those states requires some basic knowledge
of the laws governing the use of lethal force in self-defense, but
only three of the five expressly require range time. (Again, depending
on the instructor, licensees may have to demonstrate their skills in
firing and handling a gun at a range; the statute simply does not
specify it).
Only one state, Alaska, specifies
an objective or specified measure of minimum shooting proficiency.
Alaska provides that the licensing authority will approve handgun
training courses, including the NRA's personal protection course, that
test the applicant's (a) knowledge of Alaska law relating to firearms
and the use of deadly force, (b) familiarity with the basic concepts
of the safe and responsible use of handguns, (c) knowledge of
self-defense principles, and (d) physical competence with each type of
handgun the applicant wishes to carry under the permit and the maximum
caliber for each type the applicant wishes to carry under the permit.
"Competence with a handgun" is further defined as meaning
"the ability to place in a life size silhouette target (a) seven
out of 10 shots at seven yards; (b) six out of 10 shots at 15
yards." Unlike many police firearms proficiency tests, the Alaska
statute imposes no time restriction (e.g., 30 seconds) within which
that must be accomplished or limits on the number of "tries"
one can make during the test.
Arizona provides that the training
course must be at least 16 hours in length and address the following:
"legal issues relating to the use of deadly force; weapon care
and management; mental conditioning for the use of deadly force; safe
handling and storage of weapons; marksmanship; judgmental
shooting." Oklahoma provides that the course "shall be
designed and conducted in such a manner that the course can be
reasonably completed . . . within an eight-hour period." The
course content must include "a safety inspection of the firearm
to be used by the applicant in the training course; instruction on
pistol handling, safety and storage, dynamics of ammunition and
firing; methods or positions for firing a pistol; information about
the criminal provisions of the Oklahoma law relating to firearms; the
requirements of the [licensing statute] . . .; self-defense and use of
appropriate force; a practice shooting session; and a familiarization
course."
Utah provides that the training
course must include instruction in "(i) the safe loading,
unloading, storage, and carrying of the types of firearms to be
concealed; and (ii) current laws defining lawful use of a firearm by a
private citizen, including lawful self-defense, use of deadly force,
transportation and concealment."
The Case for Shall-Issue
Licensing Systems
The case for shall-issue licensing
is based on three primary arguments: (a) the right of self-defense,
(b) a social utility argument that those laws deter crime, and (c) the
constitutional right to "bear" arms without governmental
interference. In addition, the available evidence, after 10 years'
experience in 25 states, indicates that permit holders do not create
law enforcement problems, that crimes committed by permit holders
involving firearms are the very rare exception, and that the
predictions by critics that "Dodge City" would return and
that "blood will run in the streets" have decidedly not come
true.
The Right of Self-Defense
The argument or justification made
by those who seek to secure the right to carry firearms through
shall-issue licensing laws, as opposed to a privilege granted at the
discretion of the police, sheriff, court, or other state authority, is
based on a simple principle: the right of self-defense. That is, the
right to repel a criminal assault that threatens imminent danger of
death or grievous bodily injury. [38] Every
state recognizes the right of its citizens to use lethal force in
self-defense. Self-defense, so defined, is not lawlessness; it is in
accord with the law. It is, in fact, the same law that the police rely
on when they use lethal force. That right belongs to each person, not
merely those who are deemed to have some special or extraordinary need
as determined by the police or some other governmental authority.
Advocates of shall-issue licensing
laws note some salient realities. Approximately 87 percent of violent
crimes occur outside the home. [39] Even
assuming that the victim can "see it coming" and has the
time and ability to call the police, the police can get to the scene
within five minutes only about 28 percent of the time. [40]
The idea that police protection is a service that people can summon in
a timely fashion is a notion that is mocked by gun owners, who love to
recite the challenge, "Call for a cop, call for an ambulance, and
call for a pizza. See who shows up first."
Criminals choose the time and place
of their assaults, and they take pains to ensure that their crimes
occur when the police are not around. Criminals choose their victims,
and they take pains to choose those over whom they believe they have
an advantage, be it in the possession of a weapon, youth, strength, or
number. It is in the nature of things, therefore, that the victim will
almost certainly be alone and be at a disadvantage relative to his
assailant. The encounter will not be on equal terms; the fight will
not be "fair." Without a weapon, an "equalizer" to
overcome those natural disadvantages, it is unlikely that the victim
will have an effective means of defending himself. Without a weapon,
it is very likely that whether the victim lives or is maimed or
injured will depend largely or entirely on the mercy of his assailant.
The discretionary licensing laws
that are currently on the books succeed only in disarming those who
respect the law. Perversely, by ensuring that those who abide by the
law will not carry weapons outside the home, the law aids and abets
criminals by ensuring that they will find easy victims, for unarmed
men and women may be assaulted with greater confidence than those who
are, or might be, armed.
To make matters worse, while laws
deprive citizens of the ability to effectively defend themselves
outside the home, thereby placing citizens in the position of having
to rely on the police for their protection in extremis, it is a
settled principle of law throughout the United States that the police
have no legal duty to protect any individual citizen from crime. That
may come as a surprise to many people, but the principle holds even in
cases where the police have been grossly negligent in failing to
protect a crime victim. [41] The function
and responsibility of the police is to serve solely as a general
deterrent, for the benefit of the community as a whole; they are not
personal bodyguards. Those who would prohibit the carrying of arms for
self-defense thus bear a burden of establishing on what basis and on
what moral authority the government, having no obligation to protect
any particular individual, deprives particular individuals of the
ability--and means--to protect themselves. [42]
The most fundamental justification
for concealed-carry laws is the right to life. Each person has a right
to life, not just those who have demonstrated some special
"need" or "proper cause." Indeed, our Declaration
of Independence asserts that governments are instituted to secure the
right to life. The right to life of necessity implies the right to
maintain or continue one's life by defending it against violent
criminal assault. Yet the right to defend one's life is meaningless,
or a hollow promise, unless that right also encompasses the right to
the means necessary for the effective exercise of that right.
Thus, for example, the fundamental
right of free speech would be relatively meaningless if it only
encompassed the right to speak one's mind wherever one happened to be
standing or to shout one's opinions in a public park to those within
listening distance. The right has been rendered meaningful,
full-bodied, and effective by protection of the freedom of the press,
that is, by protection of the instrumentality by which one in fact
exercises the individual right within society.
Since the right to life implies a
right to the means to protect that life, the individual's right to his
own life necessarily implies a right to keep and bear arms suitable
for self-defense. In this place and time, that means a handgun, small
enough to be carried at almost all times. The presumption, therefore,
of a government that respects its citizens' right to life and
self-defense must be that they are permitted to carry arms to protect
themselves.
It is a matter for debate whether
any licensing system adequately honors that presumption, since all
licensing systems, by definition, are a prior restraint on the
exercise of liberty, and a conditional right is not really a right at
all but a privilege. However, the licensing system that most accords
with this principle is a shall-issue system. Under such a system, the
right is subject to reasonable restrictions designed to provide
reasonable assurance to the public that those who are granted permits
will not be a danger to others. Arguments may be made concerning just
what those criteria are, but the fundamental point is that the
presumption and reality must be that law-abiding adults have a right
to protect themselves from lethal criminal assault with means
effective for that purpose, when and where they need to do so, and not
just in their homes.
Social Utility
The Lott-Mustard Study. With
the publication of the Lott-Mustard study, "Crime, Deterrence and
Right-to-Carry Concealed Handguns," [43]
advocates of shall-issue licensing systems have significant
criminological support for the claim that shall-issue systems save
lives, prevent rapes and robberies, and confer benefits that extend
well beyond those garnered by the people who are issued the permits.
Analyzing crime data from all 3,054 counties in the United States
throughout the period 1977-92, Lott and Mustard found that when
shall-issue licensing laws went into effect in a county, murders fell
by 7.65 percent, rapes fell by 5.2 percent, robberies fell by 2.2
percent, and aggravated assaults fell by 7 percent. In 1992 there were
18,469 murders, 79,272 rapes, 538,368 robberies, and 861,103
aggravated assaults in counties that did not have shall-issue
licensing systems. Had those counties had such laws, Lott and Mustard
found, there would have been 1,414 fewer murders, 4,177 fewer rapes,
11,898 fewer robberies, and 60,363 fewer aggravated assaults. On the
other hand, property crime rates increased 2.7 percent--after the
passage of shall-issue laws--so there would have been 247,165 more
property crimes. Lott and Mustard conclude that criminals respond to
the threat of being shot by victims by substituting less risky,
nonconfrontational crimes. The results further showed that, while
passage of shall-issue laws resulted in immediate altered violent
crime rates, an additional reduction occurred over time, and that for
most violent crimes like murder, rape, and aggravated assault,
concealed-weapon laws had the greatest deterrent effect in counties
with high crime rates.
The results were obtained after
taking into account and factoring out the effect of other variables
that could account for the reduction in violent crime, such as changes
in population, income levels, racial and age breakdown, changes in
arrest rates, conviction rates, increased sentencing penalties, and
changes in other gun control laws. For example, one of the other
conclusions an analysis of the data provided was that waiting periods
appear to have no effect on the violent crime rate.
Using a method pioneered by the
National Institute of Justice for estimating the economic losses
associated with crime--losses from fear, pain, and suffering; lost
productivity; property losses; out-of-pocket expenses such as medical
bills; and lost quality of life--Lott and Mustard calculate that, had
those counties without shall-issue licensing systems had such laws,
they would have realized a savings of $6.2 billion, in 1992 dollars,
while the cost of the increase in property crimes would have been $417
million, resulting in a net savings of $5.74 billion. More important,
the study estimates that the issuance of each additional
concealed-carry permit reduces victim losses by up to $5,000, with the
result that "concealed handguns are the most cost-effective
method of reducing crime thus far analyzed by economists, providing a
higher return than increased law enforcement or incarceration, other
private security devices, or social programs like early educational
intervention." [44]
Because of the possibility, often
raised by critics of concealed-carry laws, that increased carrying of
handguns would result in increases in accidental deaths from firearms,
Lott and Mustard also examined the effect of shall-issue laws on the
accidental death rate from firearms. Their analysis showed that the
accidental handgun death rate rose by about 0.5 percent when
shall-issue concealed handgun laws were passed. Because the number of
accidental handgun deaths is already low (156 in the United States in
1988), their analysis predicts that implementing shall-issue licensing
systems in the states that do not have them would have resulted in
less than one (.851) more death.
Similarly, critics of shall-issue
licensing laws sometimes argue that passage of those laws will spark
an "arms race" among ordinary citizens and criminals, with
the result that more criminals will begin carrying guns and be quicker
to use them. [45] Lott and Mustard examined
whether criminals were committing more murders with guns in response
to the risk that their intended victims might be also be carrying
arms. Their analysis showed that passage of shall-issue licensing laws
was associated with equal drops in both gun and nongun murders. They
report that "carrying concealed handguns appears to make all
types of murders relatively less attractive." [46]
Apparently, criminals are not overly committed to the sporting notion
of a "fair fight"; they are looking for easy prey.
Criticism of Lott-Mustard.
Despite its careful research, the Lott-Mustard study is not immune to
serious criticism. In December 1996 the Center for the Prevention of
Handgun Violence held a forum at the National Press Club in
Washington, D.C., to address the Lott-Mustard study. Lott presented
the study's findings, and they were criticized by Professors Jens
Ludwig of Georgetown University and Daniel Nagin of Carnegie Mellon
University. Subsequently, Professors Nagin and Dan A. Black, also of
Carnegie Mellon University, have written a paper, "Do
Right-to-Carry Laws Deter Violent Crime?" that criticizes the
Lott-Mustard study. At the National Press Club forum and in that
paper, Ludwig, Black, and Nagin argue that their independent analyses
suggest that other, unspecified factors account for the decreases in
crime reported by Lott and Mustard and that there is simply no good
evidence that concealed-carry laws have any effect on
crime--that is, either a good effect or a bad effect. Some of the
objections seem well-founded and, pending further analysis, may in
fact undercut Lott and Mustard's findings, or prove them wrong.
Ludwig raised several important
objections at the National Press Club forum. First, he noted that
there was no evidence that more people were carrying concealed weapons
after the laws went into effect than before. That is, permit holders
may be people who carried guns illegally before the law went into
effect. If approximately the same number of persons carried guns
before and after the law, it is more difficult to attribute the
decline in violent crime rates to the law. [47]
The Lott-Mustard study itself points out that problem but does not
address it. However, even if the number of persons carrying concealed
firearms did not significantly change, it is possible that the law
could still account for a decrease in violent crime because the
publicity associated with the law serves to notify criminals that
citizens may be carrying guns. Such a theory could account, for
example, for the fact that, according to the Lott-Mustard study, the
violent crime rates appear to drop quite quickly after the mere
enactment of the law, despite the fact that it obviously takes time
for any significant number of permits to be issued. Of course,
proceeding on that "law-as-publicity" theory, it is also
possible that criminals overestimate their chances of encountering an
armed victim, and that the decrease is attributable to an overreaction
on their part. It may be that, if they had known the truth about how
few permit holders there were (generally, they do not exceed 5 percent
of the state's population), crime rates would not have fallen as far
as Lott and Mustard conclude that they did, or that as the criminals'
experience confirms that most people are not carrying guns, crime
rates could again rise.
Second, Ludwig noted that
concealed-carry laws would be expected to have the greatest effect on
crimes committed in public spaces, where persons, but for
concealed-carry laws, would not otherwise have access to a gun. The
violent crime most committed in public is robbery, which occurs
anywhere from 50 to 67 percent of the time in public spaces, according
to Ludwig. Yet Lott and Mustard show that concealed-carry laws had the
least effect on such crimes (a decrease of 2.2 percent) and had a far
greater effect on reducing murders (7.65 percent) and rapes (5.2
percent)--crimes that occur more often in the home or other nonpublic
spaces. According to Ludwig, that counter-intuitive result suggests
that something else might be accounting for some or all of the
decrease in crime rates that Lott and Mustard observed. Lott did not
attempt to address that issue at the National Press Club meeting, but
the Lott-Mustard study does so. Robbery includes not only street
robbery but also commercial robberies, service station and convenience
store robberies, residence robberies, and bank robberies. Given that
the FBI data on robberies include many categories of robberies besides
those that take place between strangers on a street, "it is not
obvious," Lott and Mustard note, "why this should exhibit
the greatest sensitivity to concealed handgun laws." [48]
In other words, Ludwig's intuition is just that--an intuition--and he
needs more to make his case.
Third, Ludwig noted that carrying
concealed weapons was permissible only for adults. Since juveniles are
not permitted to carry guns in any event, only violent crimes
affecting adults should affect the crime rates for adults. If juvenile
crimes are mixed in, it is possible that a large decrease in crime
against juveniles would explain the Lott-Mustard results. Ludwig
pointed out that Lott did not control for crimes against juveniles and
that the Florida homicide data for the period Lott and Mustard studied
showed that the juvenile homicide rate fell but that the homicide rate
for adults rose slightly. An analysis that factors out violent crimes
perpetrated by juveniles against juveniles might, therefore, undermine
the Lott-Mustard results. It is possible that Ludwig is correct.
However, it is also possible that juveniles will commit fewer violent
crimes against other juveniles as a result of the fact that adults are
carrying handguns. Apart from schools, where of course guns do not
exist because schools are legislated "gun-free zones,"
juveniles inhabit a world populated by adults and must therefore
reckon on the possibility that an adult, possibly armed, may stumble
upon them while they are victimizing another juvenile. That may have a
"chilling effect" on their criminal activity. [49]
Black and Nagin note that the
Lott-Mustard study makes two assumptions: first, that the impact of
shall-issue licensing laws is the same across all 10 states that
passed the laws in the period 1977 to 1992 (the "geographic
aggregation assumption") and, second, that the laws have an
impact on crime rates that is constant over time (the "intertemporal
aggregation assumption"). By performing additional analyses on
the Lott-Mustard data, Black and Nagin endeavor to disaggregate the
results in 10 separate states. The results cause them to reject Lott
and Mustard's assumption that shall-issue licensing laws may be
expected to have a uniform (positive) effect in all states:
The estimates are disparate.
Murders decline in Florida, but increase in West Virginia. Assaults
fall in Maine, but increase in Pennsylvania. Nor are the estimates
consistent within states. Murders increase, but rapes decrease in
West Virginia. Moreover, the magnitudes of the estimates are often
implausibly large. The . . . estimates imply that RTC
[right-to-carry] laws increased murders 105 percent in West Virginia
but reduced aggravated assaults by 67 percent in Maine. While one
could ascribe the effects to the RTC laws themselves, we doubt that
any model of criminal behavior could account for the variation we
observe in the signs and magnitudes of these parameters. Widely
varying estimates such as these are classic evidence that, even
beyond the assumption of homogenous impacts across states, the model
is misspecified. [50]
In other words, Black and Nagin
found that not only is it unreasonable to expect that shall-issue
licensing laws will have approximately the same positive effects in
each separate state that enacts them, but that the wild variations of
both positive and negative effects from state to state and within
states for different categories of violent crimes made it highly
likely that the Lott-Mustard study was simply wrong in attributing the
positive effects it reports to the shall-issue licensing laws. Other
factors, not adequately accounted for in the study, were at work,
creating false results. In fact, the large variation in results
suggested to Black and Nagin that the Lott-Mustard results could be
biased and driven by a single case for which their model does a poor
job of accounting for the data, and Black and Nagin found reason to
suspect that was true for Florida. When they isolated the results for
Florida, they discovered that those results accounted for 80 percent
of the total social benefit of the shall-issue licensing laws under
the Lott-Mustard study. In other words, Black and Nagin claim that the
evidence of the deterrent value of shall-issue laws vanished with the
removal of Florida from the analysis. The data from the other states
demonstrated no significant effect on violent crime rates from
concealed-carry laws.
At the National Press Club forum,
Nagin argued that there were two major social upheavals in Florida
during the period that might have caused the Florida rates to rise to
otherwise unusual heights and then fall dramatically as law
enforcement rallied to bring them under control--the Mariel boat-lift
and the emergence of South Florida as a major drug trafficking center.
It is possible that other factors associated with those events account
for the "decrease" observed by Lott and Mustard, not the
concealed-carry laws.
Black and Nagin also argue that,
when they performed additional analyses to test the Lott-Mustard
study's "intertemporal assumption," they also find no
significant evidence that the shall-issue laws have any impact on
crime rates. Rates were declining for homicide, rape, and assault in
certain states prior to adoption of the laws and continued to decline
after their passage. Black and Nagin's point, in part, is that, since
the Lott-Mustard study does not or cannot capture and isolate the
factors causing the downward trend in violent crime rates that began
before the licensing laws were enacted, it cannot specify to what
extent the downward trend after enactment is caused by licensing laws.
Again, such findings suggest not only that the intertemporal
assumption made by Lott and Mustard is wrong but also that the
"results" it attributes to shall-issue licensing laws are in
fact attributable to other factors not taken into account in their
model.
At the National Press Club forum,
Lott was given some time to rebut Black and Nagin's arguments. He
denied that his results depended solely on Florida and showed a graph
of similar decreases calculated from his data excluding Florida. He
also showed graphs to rebut Black and Nagin's arguments that
homicides, rapes, and assaults were all declining prior to enactment
of the shall-issue licensing laws. Lott introduced other
criminologists from other universities who had confirmed his results
and were running further studies using his data. Presumably other
analyses, pro and con, will be forthcoming.
Lott's Rebuttal. In an
unpublished paper dated September 17, 1997, entitled, "The
Concealed Handgun Debate," Lott makes a rigorous demonstration of
why each and every one of Black and Nagin's claims is wrong. Lott not
only claims to identify serious methodological flaws or shortcomings
with the Black-Nagin criticisms (e.g., "Black and Nagin's use of
quadratic individual state time trends makes it impossible for their
reported estimates to test any individual state level impacts from the
concealed handgun laws") [51] but also
presents new and additional evidence of the impact of the shall-issue
licensing laws across states and over time to demonstrate that the
original Lott-Mustard findings hold and that Black and Nagin's
analysis is in error.
Lott purports to show that the
results from the original Lott-Mustard study, excluding Florida,
produce "only a few, very small differences from his original
findings." [52] Moreover, he notes
that "despite legitimate interest in seeing whether the results
are sensitive to inclusion of a single state, the reasons given by
Black and Nagin for excluding Florida are factually wrong. Figure 3
depicts the murder rate in Florida from the early 1980's until 1992.
The Mariel boat lift did dramatically raise violent crime rates like
murder, but these rates had returned to their pre-Mariel levels by the
early 1980's. For murder, the rate was extremely stable until the
concealed handgun law passed there in 1987, when it began to drop
dramatically." [53]
Further, Lott notes that some of
the erratic or disparate results from state to state cited in Black
and Nagin's paper as a basis for believing that the Lott-Mustard model
is misspecified result from Black and Nagin's approach of excluding
all counties under 100,000 population in their analysis.
"Counties with more than 100,000 people are rare in some states
so it can be misleading to label estimates from these counties as
representing what is happening in these states. For example, Black and
Nagin discuss the results for West Virginia, yet in West Virginia they
have examined only one single county-–Kanawha. The other 54 counties
in West Virginia, with 89 percent of the state's population, were
excluded from their estimates." [54]
Black and Nagin argue, on the other hand, that it is necessary to
exclude counties with small populations to avoid false or misleading
results due to large percentage increases or decreases attributable to
a small number of crimes. For example, a county of small population
that goes from one murder in year 1 to two murders in year 2 has
experienced a 100 percent increase in the murder rate.
So, Do Shall-Issue Licensing
Laws Have Social Utility? The lay person who lacks the necessary
econometric tools has no independent way of resolving the conflicting
claims regarding the validity of the Lott-Mustard study and must wait
for further publications and a scholarly consensus to develop on this
issue, in hopes that one day we will all know the truth about what
happened in the period 1977-1992. (Since 1992, of course, more states
have enacted such laws, and doubtless a repeat analysis will
eventually be done with expanded data.) At present then, lay persons
cannot say whether shall-issue concealed-carry laws in fact deter
violent crime. It is too early to tell whether Lott and Mustard's
findings will emerge intact from the intense scrutiny now being
brought to bear on them or whether the critics' position, that
shall-issue licensing laws have no demonstrable effect on crime rates,
will prevail.
Nonetheless, it is remarkable that
while critics of concealed-carry laws argue that they will result in
more deaths, more accidents, and greater mayhem, the social scientists
criticizing the Lott-Mustard study are arguing only that the
concealed-carry laws have no measurable or provable effect on
crime--that is, neither a positive effect nor an adverse effect. That,
as Lott himself has noted, is a major turning point in the debate over
the social utility of firearms.
Thus, even if shall-issue licensing
laws do not benefit society as a whole to any significant extent by
deterring crime, it is also true that they do not appear to increase
crime or result in a greater number of accidents. After intense
scrutiny of 15 years of national data, there is no rigorous
comprehensive economic analysis supporting the view that such laws are
a danger to public safety. In a free society, the burden of proof is
borne by those who would restrict the liberty of others. Opponents of
shall-issue licensing laws seem to be lacking in hard criminological
data or analysis justifying their desire to prevent persons who
satisfy the licensing standards from carrying arms for self-defense.
Indeed, on that basis (that there is no demonstrable downside to the
licensing laws), advocates of shall-issue licensing systems are free
to make the argument favored by Handgun Control Inc. in support of the
Brady Act, and with equal moral authority: "If it saves just one
life, . . . "
Relevance of the Constitution
It is not necessary to appeal to
the Second Amendment to make strong arguments for shall-issue
licensing systems. Some advocates of shall-issue licensing systems do
invoke the U.S. Constitution, however, and some advocates assert
rights under state constitutional guarantees to carry arms for
self-defense. The Second Amendment provides, "A well-regulated
militia being necessary to the security of a free state, the right of
the people to keep and bear arms shall not be infringed." Some
state constitutional guarantees (such as West Virginia's) refer
expressly to a right of individuals to keep and bear arms for
self-defense or have been interpreted by state supreme courts as
providing such a right, and shall-issue licensing systems in those
states are effectively constitutionally required. [55]
It is beyond the scope of this
study to resolve the debate over whether the Second Amendment affirms
an individual right to keep and bear arms or only a right of the
states to maintain their own militias. Proponents of the latter,
"states' right" view, would claim that the Second
Amendment's right to "bear" arms is limited to the carrying
of arms as part of a citizen's service in a state militia. [56]
The implication suggested by proponents of that view is that the
states, and the federal government, are free to enact restrictions on
the ownership or carrying of weapons outside of militia service. [57]
The overwhelming weight of modern legal and historical scholarship
regarding the Second Amendment, however, is that the amendment affirms
an individual right to keep and bear private arms. [58]
As summarized by the historian Joyce Lee Malcolm,
The Second Amendment was meant to
accomplish two distinct goals, each perceived as crucial to the
maintenance of liberty. First, it was meant to guarantee the
individual's right to have arms for self-defense and
self-preservation. Such an individual right was a legacy of the
English bill of rights. This is also plain from American colonial
practice, the debates over the constitution, and state proposals for
what was to become the Second Amendment. . . .
The second and related objective
concerned the militia, and it is the coupling of these two
objectives that has caused the most confusion. The customary
American militia necessitated an armed public, and Madison's
original version of the amendment, as well as those suggested by the
states, describe the militia as either "composed of" or
"including" the body of the people. A select militia was
regarded as little better than a standing army. [59]
Most of the Second Amendment
literature, however, has focused on the question of whether the
amendment affirms an individual right, a right of the states, or a
right of the individual to serve in state militias, and has focused on
the limitations on federal or state laws restricting firearms ownership.
Very little attention has been given to the scope of what the
amendment guaranteed by way of the right to "bear" arms.
There is strong evidence, however, that suggests that the amendment
was presumed to affirm the right of private individuals to carry
weapons, either openly or concealed, for their private self-defense,
subject to the common law restriction that one could not carry arms
that were apt to terrify the public or in such manner as to make an
affray of the peace, and that the right to carry arms was regarded as
a "privilege and immunity" of American citizenship. [60]
For example, the notorious decision
in Dred Scott, in which the Supreme Court held that free blacks
were not citizens of the United States, listed, among a number of
rights and privileges that free blacks would have if they were to be
regarded as citizens, the rights to hold public meeting upon political
affairs, and "to carry arms wherever they went." [61]
Chief Justice Taney's evident intention in listing the privileges and
immunities of citizenship to which free blacks would be entitled was
to demonstrate that the Southerners who helped write the Constitution
could not possibly have intended such an absurd state of affairs. [62]
Similarly, the Freedmen's Bureau
Act of 1866, enacted by Congress to restore the civil rights of the
freed slaves following the enactment by Southern states of the
notorious Black Codes, provided that "the right . . . to have
full and equal benefit of all laws and proceedings concerning personal
liberty, personal security, . . . including the constitutional right
to bear arms, shall be enjoyed by all the citizens of such State or
district without respect to race or color or previous conditions of
slavery." [63] Later, in introducing
the Fourteenth Amendment, Sen. Jacob Howard explained that its purpose
was to protect "personal rights," including "the right
to keep and bear arms" from state infringement. [64]
Although the Supreme Court has found most of the protections in the
Bill of Rights applicable to the state governments through the
doctrine of incorporation under the due process clause of the
Fourteenth Amendment, it appears that Senator Howard viewed the right
to keep and bear arms as a "privilege and immunity" of
citizenship.
At this time, there appears to be
insufficient scholarly investigation or consensus on the scope of the
right to carry arms for self-defense intended to be protected by the
Second Amendment. If it in fact was intended to protect a right of
citizens to carry handguns for self-protection, either openly or
concealed, as a privilege and immunity of citizenship, it is possible
that licensing could be regarded as an unconstitutional prior
restraint on the exercise of a right constitutionally required to be
recognized in each state as a privilege and immunity of citizenship.
In that view, shall-issue licensing systems are regarded by some
supporters as "a good first step" to the full restoration of
rights intended to be guaranteed by the Second Amendment, while other
staunch Second Amendment advocates regard them as a potentially
dangerous precedent entrenching an incursion upon the original right.
The Experience of States with
Licensing Laws
From the available evidence, the
experience of states that have enacted shall-issue licensing systems
demonstrates that (a) almost no person with a criminal history applies
for a permit; (b) permit holders do not become embroiled in arguments
or traffic disputes leading to gun battles or "take the law into
their own hands" (or such is the very rare exception), despite
dire predictions by opponents of the laws that "blood will run in
the streets"; (c) shall-issue licensing states have almost no
problems with violent criminality among permit holders; and (d) some
permit holders have used their weapons to defend themselves. As of
this writing, shall-issue licensing laws are creating no reported law
enforcement problem in any of the 25 states that have enacted them.
After 10 years, there appears to be no reported case of any permit
holder adjudged guilty of murder committed outside the home or
licensee's business premises (the only locations where permits would
come into play) with a handgun carried in public. In general, the
number of persons in possession of permits to carry firearms at any
given time generally ranges from less than 1 percent to 5 percent of
the state's population. Of course, the mere fact that a person
possesses a permit does not mean that he is carrying a gun at any or
every given moment in time. [65] Not
everybody is carrying a gun (at least legally).
The best and most readily available
evidence is from Florida and Texas, as those states are required by
their licensing statutes to keep centralized statistical records. From
October 1, 1987, to August 31, 1997, Florida received 466,489
applications. A total of 1,676 of those were denied, 873 for criminal
history and 803 for incomplete application. A total of 457,299
licenses were issued, of which 208,089 were valid and outstanding on
August 31, 1997. That represents about 1.6 percent of Florida's
population of 12.9 million.
A total of 915 licenses have been
revoked, 313 of which were for a crime prior to licensure and
486 of which were for a crime after licensure, 85 of which
involved a firearm. [66] Thus, of the
457,299 licensees, approximately 1 in 5,000 (0.0186 percent, to be
precise) had a license revoked for a crime involving a firearm.
Only 1,186 of 466,489 applicants
(0.25 percent) had a prior criminal history constituting grounds for
denial of a permit. Criminals, in other words, are not applying for
permits to carry guns. Further, since only 602 licenses (0.13 percent)
were revoked (excluding the 313 revoked for crimes committed prior to
licensure), permit holders are not creating law enforcement problems.
From September 1987 to August 1992,
the Dade County police kept records of all arrest and nonarrest
incidents involving permit holders in Dade county. During that period,
there were four cases involving criminal misuses of firearms by permit
holders, including two cases of aggravated assault and one accidental
and nonfatal shooting. In the same period, there were seven cases
involving the defensive use of firearms, including two thwarted
robberies, one thwarted rape, and one case in which a robber disarmed
the permit holder. [67] Cramer and Kopel
report that the tracking program "was abandoned in the Fall of
1992 because of the rarity of incidents involving carry permit
holders." [68]
As of the end of 1996, there were
approximately 111,400 Texans licensed to carry handguns concealed, or
about 0.66 percent of the state's population of 16,986,500. Only 1,202
applicants had been denied permits, and there had been about 57
"incidents" involving licensees, mostly for possessing a gun
while intoxicated or for failing to conceal the weapon. As reported in
the Texas Lawyer, in the first year the law was effective
(1996), no civil suits had been filed, whether wrongful death claims
or claims against property owners, and no significant criminal charges
had been pressed against licensees solely on the basis of a newly
allowed concealed handgun. [69]
One death can be traced to the new
law–-it happened during the highly reported incident that occurred
in Dallas in February 1996 involving an argument that ensued when a
delivery van and a pickup truck scraped their sides, causing minor
damage to the vehicles side-view mirrors. [70]
The drivers stopped, an argument ensued, and one man began punching
the driver of the other vehicle in the head through the open window.
The seated driver, a licensed permit holder, drew his gun and shot his
assailant, killing him. In March the grand jury refused to indict,
evidently convinced that the shooter had acted in lawful self-defense.
[71]
Common Objections to
Shall-Issue Licensing
Arguments opposing the adoption of
shall-issue licensing systems generally fall into seven categories:
(a) a paternalistic "the police know best" argument for
retaining discretionary systems; (b) police officer safety; (c) the
potential danger to the citizen from carrying a firearm; (d) inability
of ordinary citizens to successfully defend themselves with a firearm;
(e) the inadequacy of firearms for self-defense; (f) the general
threats to public safety resulting from firearms; and (g) the most
common and basic argument, best summed up in the phrase, "the
blood will run in the streets."
The Police Know Best
Opponents of concealed-carry laws
occasionally argue for the retention of the discretionary systems on
the basis that the police are uniquely qualified, because of the
nature of their work and their experience, and uniquely positioned to
determine, because of their knowledge of the community they serve in,
precisely which applicants may be safely entrusted with to carry arms.
It would be dangerous or imprudent, the argument runs, to override
their judgment in such matters by replacing it with a rigid objective
standard that permits practically any law-abiding citizen to carry
arms.
That "trust the
professionalism of the police" argument has great appeal in
certain quarters, but it suffers from at least two problems. First, it
eliminates the presumption that individuals have the right to defend
themselves and makes the citizen a supplicant for that privilege by
placing the burden on the applicant to demonstrate to the satisfaction
of a police officer his worthiness or need to carry. Second, the
argument is completely belied by at least 60 years of experience with
discretionary licensing laws, which demonstrates that the issuance of
permits under discretionary systems has little to do with rational
determinations of who is likely to act responsibly when carrying a
gun--the sole matter that ought to be of concern to the public at
large. The power that is conferred on the government under
discretionary licensing systems is so broad and uncircumscribed that
there is nothing to prevent the police from acting arbitrarily. In
arguing for the continuation of discretionary systems, the opponents
of shall-issue licensing are arguing for government by men, not by
law.
Police Officer Safety
Another common objection is that
the carrying of handguns by law-abiding citizens jeopardizes the
safety of the police by increasing the risk that they will be shot,
either by hot-headed, previously law-abiding citizens or in shoot-outs
involving previously law-abiding citizens now taking the law into
their own hands. As a Handgun Control Inc. (HCI) pamphlet,
"Carrying Concealed Weapons--Questions and Answers," avers,
"It is our nation's police officers who are at the greatest risk
from the NRA's CCW [carry concealed weapon] campaign, and . . . under
these laws, police officers must assume that everyone is carrying a
firearm and willing to take the law into their own hands; every verbal
confrontation, at a bar, in a restaurant, at a traffic stop, could
become a potential gun battle."
Note that according to the HCI
pamphlet, it is not the nation's criminals, the permit holders
themselves, or general members of the public who are most likely to
suffer from laws permitting concealed-carry but the nation's police
officers, when previously law-abiding citizens decide that the best
way to handle a "verbal confrontation" with a policeman is
to shoot him, thereby trading up from whatever infraction the officer
was speaking to them about to the crime "cop killer."
Alternatively, the HCI pamphlet could be read as implying that police
officers are in greater danger because they will be involved in more
gun battles as previously law-abiding citizens with permits start
settling their disputes with gunfire. That is a textbook case of
hysteria. There are no reported cases of a permit holder's shooting
down, or even shooting at, a police officer.
The Citizen's Danger to
Himself or His Loved Ones
Opponents of shall-issue licensing
laws sometimes argue that guns are far more dangerous to those who
possess them or use them for self-defense than they are to criminals,
suggesting that state legislators would do well to restrict their use
and to vote against shall-issue licensing laws. The arguments are
that, by having a gun, one creates the risk that one will shoot
oneself or another by accident, that one will have available a ready
means to quit life in an impulsive moment of dark despair or to
intentionally murder a loved one or a friend in an impulsive moment
during a heated exchange, and that the likelihood of those
events far exceeds the likelihood that one will employ the weapon to save
life. Typically, supporters of those claims cite the conclusion of a
public health article that appeared in the New England Journal of
Medicine--that a gun in the home is 43 times more likely to be
used in a suicide, criminal homicide, or accidental gunshot death than
to kill in self-protection. [72] While that
study measured the risk of firearm ownership in the home and not in
public, the only place where concealed-carry laws have relevance,
those who cite it implicitly ask that we make the assumption that if
firearms are that dangerous to those who own or use them in the home,
they are likely to be dangerous everywhere. Alternatively, they might
intend for legislators, and the rest of us, to question whether the
perceived additional peace of mind gained from carrying a gun on city
streets is worth the increased risk in the citizen's home life.
There are a number of serious
problems with the "43 times" statistic. First, the study
measures the social benefits of firearms ownership only in terms of a
"body count" of dead criminals, ignoring the number of times
firearms may be used to deter crimes without having to kill the
assailant. Criminologist Gary Kleck has found that over 75 percent of
the time firearms are used defensively; they are not fired. [73]
In other words, the mere display of a firearm is, most of the time,
all that is necessary to bring about an end to the crime. Measuring
the social benefits of firearm ownership by body count is no less
misguided than measuring the benefits of the police solely by the
number of criminals they kill each year.
Second, over half of the deaths on
the 43 times side are suicides. Including them all presupposes that
none of those desperate souls would have committed suicide but for the
presence of a gun--an unlikely proposition.
Third, it is not surprising that
Kellerman and Reay's analysis shows that homicide victims are armed in
disproportionate numbers, for it appears that a large and growing
proportion of homicide victims are criminals themselves. [74]
In other words, by focusing his analysis on households in which
homicides occurred, Kellerman and Reay may be finding out information
only about the characteristics of homicide victims, and people who
commit murder, without any assurance that such information may be
safely generalized to the gun-owning public at large. It is possible
that the households in which homicides occur are far from
representative of typical or average households in which guns are
present. If so, treating the 43 times statistic as though it were a
universal law applicable to all gun owners, rather than as descriptive
of a discrete, aberrant subset, is simply wrong and misleading.
Thus, while it is tautologically
true that one cannot have an accident with a gun, commit suicide with
a gun, or kill a loved one or friend in a moment of anger with a gun
unless one first has a gun, there is no good evidence to support
claims that those possibilities are more likely and prevalent
occurrences for the typical gun owner-–and a greater risk to the
typical gun owner or his family members--than are the potential
benefits of gun ownership.
Ordinary Citizens Lack the
Necessary Competence
Many objections to concealed-carry
permits relate in some fashion to the inadequacy of training
requirements. The import, though, is not fundamentally different from
that of objections discussed elsewhere--that because of unrealistic
expectations regarding the utility of firearms for self-defense, or
insufficient or inadequate training, citizens who carry firearms will
be a danger to themselves and others.
In most cases, the argument is
essentially that the 8 to 16 hours of training required to obtain a
concealed-carry permit are insufficient to properly prepare anyone to
carry a gun and can only result in false confidence and insufficient
skill. The argument has commonsensical appeal, and the opponents of
shall-issue licensing systems are not in error in pointing out such
possibilities. However, as a review of the experience of states with
shall-issue licensing systems illustrates, there is little to no
evidence, after 10 years, to support the proposition that those
potential adverse consequences actually occur with troubling
frequency. Lacking hard evidence, those who raise such objections make
reference to the experience of the police to suggest the gross
inadequacy of the requirements for permit holders.
For example, the Handgun Control,
Inc. pamphlet, "Carrying Concealed Weapons--Questions and
Answers," notes the following:
Importantly, police know the
dangers associated with the use of firearms. They are extensively
trained on the use and security of their service weapons, yet many
are still killed every year by guns. A recent FBI study showed that
police officers who are killed in the line of duty rarely even fire
a round at their assailant, and frequently the police officer's own
firearm is taken from him/her and used against him/her. An FBI study
of 51 incidents where 54 police officers were killed found that 85%
did not fire their weapon while 20% were killed with their own gun. [75]
In addition, consider the following
exchanges reported on an October 1, 1995, 60 Minutes episode on
the Florida licensing system:
Officer Walter Philbrick
(Firearms Instructor): Congratulations, Leslie.
Leslie Stahl: Thank you.
Officer Philbrick: You have
passed the course with flying colors.
Stahl (voiceover): The course I
passed with flying colors qualifies me to carry a concealed weapon.
And, frankly, I don't know any more now about handling a gun than I
did before I took the course.
Officer Philbrick: In the police
academy, officers get 18 weeks of training. All right? Eighteen
weeks before--before they're given that firearm to carry on duty.
Stahl (voiceover): Eighteen weeks
for a police officer, but for someone like me, who has never even
fired a weapon, a couple of hours one night in a classroom was
enough to get me a license to pack a gun. [76]
First, it is important to set aside
the hyperbole. Police do not literally receive 18 weeks of firearms
training. The Florida officers referred to in the 60 Minutes
program have 18 weeks to learn all the basic skills they need to begin
their further on-the-job training as a "rookie," including
classroom instruction in the laws they will be enforcing, witness
interview techniques, search and seizure procedures. The precise
amount of time spent in classroom study of the law of justifiable
homicide and shoot/don't shoot scenarios and firearms training at the
range would be the relevant comparison, and that information is
generally not divulged by the police, presumably because it comprises
comparatively little of the total training time, and the information
would simply be grist for the mill for lawyers representing people who
have been wrongfully shot by the police.
The remaining argument rests, for
its validity, on an assumption that the experience of the police
provides a valid and comparable basis for predicting the likely
experience of permit holders. There are several reasons to expect that
that is not true.
Permit holders need concern
themselves with only one thing: protecting themselves from a sudden,
violent assault that threatens life or grievous bodily injury. Rape,
robbery, and attempted murder are not typically actions rife with
ambiguity or subtlety, requiring special powers of observation, great
book-learning, or a stint at the police academy to discern. When a man
pulls a knife on a woman and says, "You're coming with me,"
her judgment that a crime is being committed is not likely to be in
error.
Police, by contrast, do not carry
arms solely for the purpose of defending themselves, but also for the
purpose of enforcing the law. They deliberately inject themselves into
potentially dangerous and violent situations, responding to calls for
assistance, investigating crimes, intervening in domestic violence,
and making arrests.
Consider, for example, an argument
that is not made by opponents of licensing laws but that they could
also use to suggest that citizens' carrying arms will result in
needless deaths. The police, who are "extensively trained"
in the use and security of their weapons, mistakenly kill about 330
innocent citizens a year. [77] How many
more wrongful deaths, then, might one expect at the hands of poorly
trained permit holders? Although the argument exhibits the same logic,
opponents of licensing laws do not seize on it. Doubtless that is due
in part to the fact that it does not show the police in too favorable
a light, yet it is upon them that the opponents of licensing laws are
asking us to rely when they try to disabuse us of the notion of
relying also on ourselves. But a more telling reason is that the
information is actually available to refute it. In fact, gun owners
mistakenly kill about 30 innocent persons a year, one-eleventh of the
number killed by police. [78]
Were we to adopt the reasoning of
gun control proponents in this circumstance, we might argue that such
a fact shows that citizens are more responsible with firearms than are
police, or that police culture is one of brutality. The difference
might be more innocently explained, however, by the significant
differences between the activities of the police and those of
law-abiding citizens seeking only to protect themselves, differences
that render their experiences incomparable. The intended victim is
always at the scene of the crime; he knows precisely who his tormentor
is. It is the police who, because they are rarely at the scene of the
crime when it occurs, are more likely to find themselves in situations
where guilt or innocence is not so clear-cut, and the probability for
mistakes is correspondingly higher.
In sum, there are serious problems
with the assumption that the experience of the police may serve as a
useful guide to predicting the experience of licensed permit holders,
or that the training requirements for police provide the benchmark for
the training required to carry a gun as a citizen.
According to criminologist Gary
Kleck, guns are fired in only about 24 percent of the cases in which
they are used for self-defense. [79] Thus,
in the overwhelming majority of cases in which a gun is used in
self-defense, the gun is never fired. The point of this is not
that training is not necessary because most of the time brandishing or
displaying the gun serves as a magic talisman to ward off evil. The
real significance of that number is that people using guns for
self-defense are not "trigger-happy."
In other words, we do not need to
develop a course of both physical and moral training based on the
assumption that the law-abiding citizens who seek permits to carry
guns are Rambo or Dirty Harry wannabes who view violent crimes as
opportunities to put notches on their gun handles. The statistical
information strongly suggests that we are dealing with decent people
who are loath to kill and who truly view killing as an act of last
resort. Possibly, that is because they are acutely aware, from media
coverage of the Bernhard Goetz case, the intense scrutiny of
questionable police shootings, and the national attention given to
mistaken shootings like that involving the Japanese exchange student
in Louisiana, that at a minimum, if they shoot they are in for a world
of legal trouble. Possibly, to take an approach that does not reduce
all human activity to quanta of pleasure and pain for the purpose of
utilitarian cost/benefit calculations, they actually value life and
are constrained by religious beliefs from precipitously taking the
life of another.
It may be that, because of the
infrequency of actual shootings by permit holders, any deficiencies in
the statutory training requirements will take considerable time to
become manifest. [80] So far, 10 years' of
evidence from the states with shall-issue licensing systems indicate
that the fears of the results of "loose" training
requirements on the part of opponents have not materialized. While all
licensing statutes should require express instruction in safe gun
handling and that applicants learn the law governing the justifiable
or excusable use of deadly force, and it would be desirable for
licensing laws to specify a reasonable proficiency standard, there
seems little reason to drastically expand the general training
requirements provided in the statutes. Some critics of shall-issue
licensing laws have reevaluated their stance on the insufficiency of
these requirements and are content with them in their current form:
"The $150 they charge will get you a damn good course,"
[District Attorney for Harris County, Texas, John] Holmes says.
"You're gonna know more about what is permissible conduct. I was
so opposed to the law that I took the instructors course, and I was
pleasantly surprised--it was very heavy on the law and how guns can
get you into more trouble than they can get you out of.'" [81]
Finally, it is important to
recognize that the critics of the training standards are somewhat
disingenuous. Their purpose in deploring the statutory training
standards does not appear to reflect a willingness to work with
legislators or gun owners to develop realistic criteria. Rather, by
suggesting that it takes much time and effort to attain sufficient
proficiency (18 weeks), they call into question the very idea of
licensing ordinary citizens to carry firearms. That is, the objections
are presented as objections to the very adoption of licensing systems,
not as proposals to refine their operation. Note that while critics of
these laws decry the low or vague training standards put in place by
the licensing statutes, one does not find them simultaneously decrying
the generally complete absence of any requirements for training or the
vague standards in the statutes creating or governing the nation's
police forces. Obviously, many, but by no means all, of the nation's
police receive some form of formal training, but they do so in
accordance with self-defined and self-imposed training standards
promulgated by internal regulations by police administrators. It is
thus revealing that, while the critics appear content to trust the
police to define and live up to their own standards, they are not
prepared to trust their fellow citizens in that regard.
The Inadequacy of Guns for
Protection
Opponents of shall-issue licensing
laws occasionally argue, or suggest, that guns are not very useful for
self-defense, or that they do not guarantee perfect protection. For
example, they argue, guns do not appear to be useful in preventing or
defending against crime, given that they are only used in defense
about 65,000 to 80,000 times a year. [82]
One might not be able to get to the weapon in time, being surprised by
the criminal before having time to respond. Even if armed, the best
course of action might be to do nothing. Even if armed, there is no
guarantee that one will not be killed anyway. The argument presented
above was that it requires great, developed judgment to know the
circumstances in which guns are the right tool for the job. The
argument here is different: that the circumstances in which guns are
really useful are so rare or infrequent that they are not worth
bothering about.
The number of defensive gun uses is
a hotly contested issue. At least two carefully crafted surveys
suggest that guns may be used for defensive purposes as many as 2
million to 3.6 million times a year. [83] A
recent paper presented at the American Society of Criminology meetings
in Chicago, Illinois, adduces numerous reasons to suspect that the
latter figure is too, or even impossibly, high, however. [84]
Assuming, arguendo, that the true number is in fact closer to 65,000,
the argument regarding the limited utility of firearms is nonetheless
not an argument against shall-issue carry laws. The fact that guns are
only rarely useful does not render them any less useful or necessary
in those circumstances in which they are precisely the right tool for
the job. The fact that firearms cannot handle all problems of personal
security does not mean they can handle no such problems.
The fallacies are easy to recognize
if one simply makes the same sort of arguments about another, less
emotion-laden tool. For example, the fact that flat tires occur only
rarely does not mean one ought not carry a car jack and spare tire.
Similarly, the fact that car jacks and spare tires are useless in
dealing with numerous other forms of auto breakdown does not mean that
car jacks are not useful devices to have at hand. Or again, the fact
that a house fire may gain too strong a foothold before one can deal
with it does not mean that there is no point in having a fire
extinguisher in one's home. So even if firearms are only rarely useful
for self-defense or cannot handle all problems of personal security,
that is not an argument against firearms, or having them at hand when
needed. If the fear is that people will not recognize firearms'
limitations or will try to use guns inappropriately, the answer is
education, not prohibition.
It is interesting that this
objection is never employed against police officers. After all, the
very same type of arguments apply: the police may not be there when
needed; the attack may occur so fast that you don't have time to call
them; they may not be able to get to you in time; the fact that they
exist or that you call them does not mean that you won't be killed
anyway; and relying on them as if they were a talisman that magically
wards off evil could create a false sense of security. Apparently,
while some opponents of concealed-carry are concerned with preventing
citizens from acting mistakenly on the basis of false ideas of utility
that result in self-reliance, they are unconcerned about false ideas
of utility that result in dependence on government.
Finally, however large or small may
be the frequency with which guns are used in self-defense, there are
some facts that have not, to date at least, been controverted by
criminologists. National Institute of Justice statistics show that
persons who resist crime with a firearm are less likely to be injured,
or are likely to be injured less severely, than persons who either
cooperate (do not resist at all) or resist by any other means.
Amazingly, that remains true even if the assailant is armed with a
gun. While opponents of concealed-carry laws disparage the idea that
ordinary citizens can successfully defend themselves, the statistical
evidence shows that, if a victim does have time to deploy a firearm,
he has enhanced his chances for survival and lessened his chances for
serious injury. [85]
More Guns Cause More Violence
In addition to arguing that the
permit holders will kill or injure others or themselves if they are
permitted to carry firearms, opponents of shall-issue licensing
systems make general arguments against any "loosening" of
the laws restricting firearms ownership or use based on the general
social harm caused by misuse of firearms. Often, the argument may be
as simple as claiming that more guns on city streets can only result
in more deaths, more injuries, and more accidents. The argument, in
its simplest form, assumes a straightforward linear correlation
between the number of guns and the number of violent crimes committed
with guns.
However intuitively true it seems
that more guns must inevitably result in more violence or gun crime,
it is well established, criminologically, that more guns do not mean
more homicides:
In 1973, the American firearm
stock totalled 122 million, the handgun stock was 36.9 million, and
the homicide rate was 9.4 per 100,000 people. At the end of 1992,
twenty years later, the firearm stock had risen to 221.9 million,
the handgun stock had risen to 77.6 million, but the homicide rate
was 8.5--or 9.5 percent lower than it had been in 1973. The
percentage of murders committed with firearms decreased as well. In
1973, 68.5 percent of murders were committed with guns. Fifteen
years later, after Americans had purchased almost as many new
firearms as they had in the preceding seventy-three years, 62.8
percent of homicides were committed with guns. . . . In sum, over a
twenty year period of unparalleled increase in guns, homicide rates
were erratic, unpatterned, and completely inconsistent with the
shibboleth that doubling the number of guns, especially handguns,
would increase homicide rates. [86]
In short, it is not the number of
guns but their distribution--that is, the people who have the guns and
what they are using them for--that matters. The available evidence
clearly indicates that firearms in the hands of permit holders are not
a law enforcement problem, are not a source of social harm, and that
irresponsible use of firearms by permit holders is the very rare
exception.
A more sophisticated approach is to
build a general case that the total social harm related to firearms
far outweighs any social benefits associated with their ownership and
use. The numbers tell a decidedly grim story: In 1994, for example,
there were approximately 1.3 million gun crimes. A few more than
22,000 people were murdered with firearms, an approximately equal
number committed suicide with firearms, and about 100,000 people were
treated in hospitals or emergency rooms for nonfatal gunshot wounds
(including self-inflicted wounds from suicide attempts and accidents).
[87] On the other hand, firearms are used
defensively (it is argued) only about 65,000 to 80,000 times a year.
The result is that the societal costs associated with firearm misuse
far exceed the societal benefits from their use.
Because of the critical importance
in utilitarian analyses, such as that outlined above, of the number of
defensive gun uses, a number of investigations have been made to
determine what that number is. [88] Two
reputable surveys specifically designed to determine the number of
defensive gun uses have found that the number is orders of magnitude
above the 65,00 to 80,000 reported by other researchers and that the
number is in the range of 2 million to 3.6 million a year. [89]
If that number is valid, guns are used far more often to defend
against crime than to perpetrate crime. Further, according to both
surveys, 45-46 percent of the gun users believed that they or someone
else might have been killed had they not used the gun in self-defense.
Even if someone's life was saved in only 5 percent of such cases,
however, the surveys imply that 100,000 (5 percent of 2 million) lives
would be saved each year by the defensive use of firearms, far
surpassing the number of lives lost to gun violence and suicide.
Criminologists Philip J. Cook and
Jens Ludwig suggest that there is reason to believe that the numbers
obtained from these surveys are high, possibly impossibly high, and
have made some arguments why the survey results might generate other
false results. They point out, for example, that some of the numbers
implied by the survey results do not accord with other statistics
generally regarded as accurate. For example, they point out that the
survey results imply that the number of women who have used a gun to
defend themselves against rape is higher than the total number of
rapes reported by the National Crime Victimization Survey (NCVS)
conducted by the Census Bureau for the U.S. Bureau of Justice
Statistics and that comparing the numbers of criminals wounded or shot
by civilian defenders with the total number treated for gunshot wounds
in hospitals and emergency rooms and those killed in assaults suggests
that large numbers of criminals who are shot never receive emergency
room treatment or become known to law enforcement, a result Cook and
Ludwig find hard to believe.
There may be good explanations for
some of the perceived discrepancies, and the discrepancies are not
necessarily indicative that the total number of defensive gun uses is
grossly in error. For example, it is known that rape is one of the
most underreported of crimes; researchers Colin Loftin and Ellen
Mackenzie reported that rapes might be 33 times as frequent as the
NCVS numbers indicate. [90] Thus, it is
quite possible that the number of defensive uses of guns to avert a
rape might approximate those reported in the NCVS. Similarly, it would
not be surprising if those firing their guns in self-defense
overestimated wounding the criminal. If the criminal flees or escapes
and is never apprehended by the police, there is no way to confirm
whether one succeeded in hitting the criminal. Respondents' subjective
impressions might easily be in error, or respondents might be
exaggerating their shooting skills.
More serious are Cook and Ludwig's
arguments concerning the possibility for survey errors due to (a)
"telescoping," that is, a survey respondent's recalling a
defensive gun use that occurred outside of the period asked about (for
example, the last five years) as happening during the period being
asked about or (b) a desire to appear heroic by claiming conspicuous
acts of self-defense. Because survey results are based on statistical
projections from a fairly small number of positive responses, a small
number of false positives can make a large difference in the outcome.
Cook and Ludwig argue that surveys
are thus a flawed method of learning about the frequency with which
innocent victims of crime use a gun to defend themselves. That
conclusion seems premature, for the bulk of their paper raises
questions by making observations and raising possible reasons why
survey results might be overstated, since they are based on
respondents' answers regarding number of criminals shot and number of
lives saved–-highly subjective matters. The fact that respondents'
subjective impressions might be highly erroneous is not, nonetheless,
necessarily good evidence that they did not actually use a gun for
defense. The fact that a person tells a "fish story"
exaggerating the size of the fish, does not mean that he did not
actually catch a fish. Thus, the number of defensive gun uses reported
by surveys may be approximately correct.
Beyond that, in addition to the
Kleck and Gertz survey and the 1994 National Survey of Private
Ownership of Fire-arms in the United States discussed by Cook and
Ludwig, 10 commercial surveys from 1976 to 1994 have included
questions about defensive gun use. Although those surveys were not
specifically designed to gather detailed information about defensive
gun use, Kleck and Gertz report that they nonetheless indicate 770,000
to 2 million defensive gun uses per year. One such survey of
particularly high quality, a 1981 survey by Hart Research Associates,
indicates 1.8 million defensive gun uses per year. Thus, there is a
remarkable degree of consistency in the results of well-designed
surveys. If respondents are lying or exaggerating the truth, they are
doing so in highly consistent ways.
While Cook and Ludwig's
observations thus deserve serious attention and investigation, it is
premature to dismiss out of hand the survey results indicating high
numbers of defensive gun uses. Were Cook and Ludwig correct, however,
that survey results are indeterminately unreliable, the result would
be that the true number of defensive gun uses would be indeterminate.
The fact that survey information may be overstated, albeit
indeterminately so, does not prove that the NCVS numbers are not
understated. In this case it would appear difficult if not impossible
to determine the amount of societal benefit derived from ownership and
use of firearms, with the result that it could also not be asserted
either that the costs outweighed those benefits or that the benefits
outweighed the costs. [91]
The end result is that if one
believes the survey information regarding the number of defensive gun
uses, and further believes that that number represents a reasonable
proxy for the societal benefit associated with firearms, then guns are
used far more often to prevent crime than to commit crime, and
probably save more lives than are lost to homicide or suicide with
guns. If one disbelieves the survey results but cannot specify to what
extent they are wrong, or if one doubts that the number of defensive
gun uses is a useful measure of societal benefit, then it appears that
one cannot make a case either way. One must have some trustworthy way
of specifying the amount of the benefit before one can measure the
direction of the inequality. Only if one believes that survey results
should be completely disregarded and that NCVS estimates of 65,000 to
80,000 defensive gun uses per year is the best evidence, is the
general utilitarian case made against guns. In that case, one must
face the question of whether an individual's right of self-defense
trumps social cost/benefit calculations, an answer to which requires
an evaluation of the ethical limits of utilitarianism, which is beyond
the scope of this study.
Blood Will Run in the Streets
The most powerful rhetorical
argument that is generally made by those who oppose shall-issue
licensing laws is that permitting law-abiding citizens to carry
handguns outside their homes will transform the streets of America
into "Dodge City." The "blood will run in the
streets," it is claimed, as law-abiding citizens take to settling
disputes and answering slights to their dignity by shooting it out.
The argument is asserted over and over again despite the fact that it
has most decidedly not been borne out by 10 years of experience in 25
states with permit holders' carrying firearms for defense.
Nevertheless, there will, in all probability, be a clear and egregious
case of a permit holder misusing his firearm sometime in the future.
And because the climate surrounding gun issues is so highly charged, a
well-publicized tragedy could obliterate all prior experience with
concealed-carry permits--at least in the minds of politicians who
favor gun control.
The fact that the "blood will
run in the streets" argument seems immune to challenge by the
facts suggests that it persists because it resonates deeply with many
people's understanding of, and beliefs about, fundamental human
nature. That is the way, in other words, those to whom this argument
has great appeal expect that people will behave, if you let
them. It is a most unflattering view.
Given the qualifications required
of permit holders, proponents of the "Dodge City" argument
can only believe that common, ordinary law-abiding citizens are
seething cauldrons of homicidal rage, ready to kill to avenge any
slight to their dignity, eager to seek out and summarily execute the
lawless. Only lack of immediate access to a gun restrains them and
prevents the blood from flowing in the streets. They are so morally
and mentally deficient that they will readily mistake their permit to
carry a weapon in self-defense as a state-sanctioned license to kill
at will. Thus are men and women creatures of unrestrained impulse,
appetite, and whim. People are basically accidents or crimes waiting
to happen. The law-abiding are only accidentally law-abiding, for they
remain law-abiding only because they lack the means to immediately act
on their fleeting and dark impulses. It is too much to ask people like
that (that is, most people), and too risky to expect people like that
(that is, most people), to exercise self-control and behave
responsibly.
Supporters of shall-issue licensing
laws make arguments that reflect a decidedly different view of their
fellow citizens--namely, that they are not creatures driven by impulse
and desire but are entitled to the trust properly accorded a moral and
rational being capable of exercising judgment and self-control.
Supporters of shall-issue licensing laws implicitly believe that a
person's character and actions do not fundamentally change merely
because he has a tool at hand with which he can more perfectly and
readily act on his fleeting impulses and desires. People who have
demonstrated self-control and responsible behavior in the past, as
evidenced by the absence of criminal, mental health, and drug
histories, will, in all likelihood, continue to act responsibly. The
act of permitting them to carry a firearm (which they already have the
de facto ability to do) will not change their character or fundamental
nature or their actions. It is not too much to expect such people--our
fellow citizens--to act responsibly; it is not too risky to trust such
people.
While criminologists wage mighty
battles to determine whether firearms have social utility or not, with
the results always promised in the next conclusive study, the reality
is that those findings are used as tools in a battle between views of
human nature. It is beyond the scope of this study to decide the
nature of man, but it is, at bottom, the warring views on that subject
that are actually driving the concealed-carry debate.
Conclusion
Since 1987, 24 states have enacted
laws requiring licensing authorities (usually, the chief of police or
county sheriff) to issue permits to carry concealed weapons to adult
state residents who have not been convicted of any felony; who have no
history of drug or alcohol abuse and no history of mental illness;
and, in most states, who have taken a firearms training course. In
nearly all cases, applicants' fingerprints are taken and the
applicants are subject to a background check. The permits generally
have a life of from two to five years and must be renewed.
In most cases, the new shall-issue
licensing laws replaced concealed-weapon licensing statutes, dating
from the 1930s and 1940s, that granted the licensing authority
(usually the police) broad, undefined discretion to issue permits to
"suitable persons" or to persons of "good moral
character" who had "proper cause" or a
"justifiable need" to carry a weapon. As written, those laws
suggest that only certain people, in "special"
circumstances, are entitled to defend themselves from deadly violence
with lethal force, and that those who face only the
"ordinary" risk of criminal violence do not deserve the
right to carry the means with which to defend themselves. The implicit
suggestion that some people's lives are more worth protecting than are
the lives of others is morally repugnant and insupportable. The
frustration of the common, law-abiding citizen's desire to protect
himself (and increasingly, herself) from violent crime has led to
vociferous demands for the replacement of those laws with licensing
regimes based on satisfaction of nondiscretionary, objectively
verifiable and enumerated criteria.
According to Department of Justice
statistics, approximately 87 percent of violent crime occurs outside
the home. Despite the fact that Americans possess approximately 70
million handguns, one is not armed if one does not have a weapon at
hand when needed. Perversely, the discretionary licensing laws and
prohibitions against the carrying of weapons succeed only in disarming
those who respect the law. Perversely, by ensuring that those who
abide by the law will not carry weapons outside the home, the law aids
and abets criminals by assuring them that they will find unarmed, easy
victims. Shall-issue concealed-carry laws, by contrast, deprive
criminals of that peace of mind.
Shall-issue licensing systems are
based on the right of self-defense, that is, the right to use lethal
force to repel a criminal assault that threatens imminent danger of
death or grievous bodily injury. Every state recognizes a right of its
citizens to use lethal force in self-defense. Self-defense, so
defined, is not lawlessness; it is in accord with the law. It is, in
fact, in accord with the same law the police rely on in using lethal
force. The right to self-defense belongs to each person, not merely
those who the police or other licensing authorities believe
"deserve" to have that right.
Opponents of the new licensing laws
argue that more guns on city streets can only lead to more violence
and deaths; that the laws will transform the streets of America into
"Dodge City," as previously law-abiding citizens take to
settling hot-headed arguments over fender benders and slights to their
dignity with guns; that the carrying of weapons by ordinary citizens
jeopardizes the safety of the police; that citizens' lack of training
will lead to false confidence in or unrealistic expectations about the
usefulness of firearms, with the possible result that license holders
will take foolish risks; that due to insufficient training, license
holders will lack good judgment in determining when it is appropriate
to shoot, resulting in wrongful shootings and wrongful brandishing of
firearms; or that insufficient proficiency with their weapons will
result in the shooting of innocent bystanders or loved ones.
While opponents of licensing laws
are not wrong to point out that those adverse results are potential
consequences of the widespread carrying of weapons, we need no longer
speculate about what the effects of such laws might be. We now have at
least 10 years of actual evidence from 25 different states with
diverse rural and metropolitan populations, including the cities of
Miami, Houston, Dallas, Pittsburgh, Philadelphia, Richmond, Atlanta,
New Orleans, Seattle, and Portland, regarding perhaps as many as 1
million permit holders carrying their weapons for hundreds of millions
of man-hours. The results are in, and they show unequivocally that (a)
the number of persons currently in possession of permits to carry
firearms ranges from 1 to 5 percent of the state's population; (b)
criminals do not apply for permits; (c) permit holders do not take to
settling their traffic disputes or arguments with guns, or "take
the law into their own hands"; (d) shall-issue licensing states
have almost no problems with violent criminality or inappropriate
brandishing of firearms by permit holders; and (e) some permit holders
have used their guns to defend themselves and others. There appears to
be no reported case of any permit holder adjudged to have wrongfully
killed another in connection with carrying and using his weapon in
public. As of this writing, shall-issue licensing laws are creating no
reported law enforcement problem in any of the 25 states that have
enacted them. Dodge City has not returned; the blood is not
running in the streets.
With the publication this year of
the Lott-Mustard study, "Crime, Deterrence and Right-to-Carry
Concealed Handguns," finding that licensing laws deter violent
crime and save lives, an intense criminological debate has begun over
whether shall-issue licensing laws in fact deter violent crime.
Notably, despite fears of opponents that the licensing laws will lead
to increased crime and violence, the criminologists criticizing the
Lott-Mustard study are arguing only that shall-issue licensing laws
have no demonstrable effect on violent crime rates, that is, they
neither decrease violent crime rates nor increase them. It remains to
be seen whether Lott and Mustard's findings will withstand the
scrutiny now being brought to bear on them, or whether the critics are
correct. However, after intense scrutiny of 10 years of national data,
there is no rigorous comprehensive economic analysis supporting the
view that shall-issue licensing laws are a danger to public safety. In
a free society, the burden of proof is borne by those who would
restrict the liberty of others. Opponents of shall-issue licensing
laws are lacking in hard criminological data and analyses condemning
those laws and justifying opponents' desire to prevent persons who
satisfy the licensing standards from carrying handguns for
self-defense.
Shall-issue licensing systems are
not, as is sometimes asserted by their opponents, another example of
America's free-wheeling, hands-off approach to guns. The licensing
systems are gun control. Applicants are registered and fingerprinted
and their backgrounds are thoroughly checked, both at the state and at
the national level through the FBI, for criminal histories, and
histories of drug or alcohol abuse and mental illness. In addition,
the great majority of states require that applicants have received
training with firearms. On the basis of 10 years of experience in 25
states, we may conclude that shall-issue licensing systems work. They
accomplish the twin goals of providing a mechanism by which
law-abiding citizens can carry the means with which to defend
themselves from a violent criminal assault that imminently threatens
life or grievous bodily harm and provide the public reasonable
assurance that those who receive permits are persons who will act
responsibly.
Notes
The author would like to thank
Timothy Lynch of the Cato Institute, Preston Covey of Carnegie Mellon
University, John R. Lott Jr. of the University of Chicago School of Law,
Don B. Kates, Daniel S. Nagin of Carnegie Mellon University, and Daniel
D. Polsby of Northwestern University School of Law for their gracious
assistance in the preparation of this study. Any and all errors are the
sole responsibility and property of the author.
1. In addition to Florida, the
following states have enacted "shall-issue" concealed-carry
laws: Alaska, Arizona, Arkansas, Georgia, Idaho, Louisiana, Maine,
Mississippi, Montana, Nevada, New Hampshire, North Carolina, Oklahoma,
Oregon, Pennsylvania, South Carolina, South Dakota, Tennessee, Texas,
Utah, Virginia, West Virginia, and Wyoming. Note that the state of
Washington has had a nondiscretionary licensing system in place since
1961. Note also that Vermont permits open- or concealed-carry for
self-defense without a license or permit. Thus, 26 states permit
lawabiding adult citizens to carry concealed arms for self-defense
outside their home on a nondiscretionary basis.
[2].
See Clayton E. Cramer, For the Defense of Themselves and the State:
The Original Intent and Judicial Interpretation of the Right to Keep and
Bear Arms (Westport, Conn.: Praeger, 1994), p. 94.
[3].
Ibid.
[4].
See Robert J. Cottrol and Raymond T. Diamond, "The Second
Amendment: Toward an Afro-Americanist Reconsideration," Georgetown
Law Journal 80 (1991): 335-42.
[5].
See Cramer, p. 96. For a more detailed discussion of the efforts to deny
arms to free blacks and slaves, see the discussion in chap. 6, pp.
71-96.
[6].
State v. Chandler, 5 La. An. 489, 490-91 (1850), cited in Cramer,
p. 88.
[7].
The Sullivan Law survives as section 400.00 of the New York Penal Law.
[8].
See Don B. Kates, "Toward a History of Handgun Prohibition in the
United States," in Restricting Handguns--The Liberal Skeptics
Speak Out (Great Barrington, Mass.: North River, 1979), p. 15.
[9].
Ibid., p. 16.
[10].
Ibid., pp. 19–22; and Cramer, pp. 97-140.
[11].
Watson v. Stone, 4 So.2d 700, 703 (1941) (Buford, J.,
concurring).
[12].
See Edward F. Leddy, Magnum Force Lobby: The National Rifle
Association Fights Gun Control (Lanham, Md.: University Press of
America, 1987), pp. 86-87; and Don B. Kates, "Handgun Prohibition
and the Original Meaning of the Second Amendment," Michigan Law
Review 82 (1983): 209-10.
[13].
See Cramer, p. 165 (describing Montana legislative history).
[14].
Lee B. Kennett and James L. Anderson, The Gun in America: The Origins
of a National Dilemma (Westport, Conn.: Greenwood, 1975), pp.
192-97, 210, 212; Leddy, pp. 86-87; and Kates, "Toward a History of
Handgun Prohibition in the United States," pp. 29-30.
[15].
One example that warrants analysis is the contemporary notion that the
use and ownership of firearms should be confined to "sporting
purposes." Without accusing anyone who recommends this standard of
having illicit or secret racist or class-based motivations, the fact
nonetheless is that hunting, target shooting, and other sporting uses of
firearms tend to be an activity engaged in predominantly if not almost
exclusively by whites, particularly rural and suburban whites, and not
the inhabitants of the inner city. In addition, "sporting use"
implicitly singles out those who have sufficient leisure and
discretionary income to pursue recreation with firearms. Ownership of
firearms is clearly associated with levels of discretionary income. See
Gary Kleck, Point Blank: Guns and Violence in America (Hawthorne,
N.Y.: Aldine de Gruyter, 1991). It is thus a noteworthy coincidence that
the selection of the criterion, "sporting use," happens to
largely leave out those who are associated in the public mind with the
source of much of the crime problem, both racially and by class. To be
sure, no laws, no genetic disposition prevents persons of any and all
races, ethnic backgrounds, and classes from pursuing the recreational
use of firearms; it is only a historical accident. Nonetheless, it is an
interesting thought experiment by which one may check one's intellectual
honesty to inquire whether the "sporting use" standard would
find as much favor if there were a preexisting and widespread tradition
of handgun and shotgun hunting among urban African-Americans and
Hispanics.
16. California Penal Code, sec.
12050 et seq.
17. Colorado Revised Statutes,
sec. 18-12-105.1.
18. New York Penal Law, sec.
400.00.
19. North Dakota Statutes, sec.
62.1-04-03.
20. Rhode Island Statutes, secs.
11-47-11, 11-47-18.
[21].
Charles Krauthammer, "Disarm the Citizenry," Washington
Post, April 5, 1996.
[22].
"Who Is Entitled to Carry Concealed Weapons," American Law
Reports 51 (3d ed., 1973): 506.
23. See Steve Garnass, "Cops
Get Tougher on Gun Permits," Denver Post, April 24, 1988, p.
A1.
[24].
Quoted in ibid.
[25].
See Clayton E. Cramer and David B. Kopel, "'Shall Issue': The New
Wave of Concealed Handgun Permit Laws," Tennessee Law Review
62 (1995): 683.
[26].
See John R. Lott Jr. and David B Mustard, "Crime, Deterrence, and
Right-to-Carry Concealed Handguns," Journal of Legal Studies
26 (1997): 8n 29.
[27].
See Don B. Kates, "Concealed Weapons Permits in California,"
an unpublished research paper.
[28].
See "Elite in NYC are Packing Heat," Boston Globe,
January 8, 1993, p. 3; William Bastone, "Born to Gun; 65 Big Shots
with Licenses to Carry," Village Voice, September 29, 1987.
Summarized in Cramer and Kopel, p. 684. See also Don B. Kates, "The
Battle over Gun Control," Public Interest 84 (1986): 45.
29. Cramer and Kopel, p. 685.
[30].
Hickman v. County of Los Angeles, cited and discussed in Cramer
and Kopel, p. 685.
[31].
See "Gun-Licensing Boss Suspended by NYPD," New York Post,
January 23, 1996, p. 26.
[32].
My thanks to Preston Covey of the Department of Applied Ethics at
Carnegie Mellon University for pointing this out.
[33].
As was pointed out in the Lott-Mustard study, the main effect of
shall-issue licensing systems has been to enable persons living in
counties with a population exceeding 100,000 persons to obtain permits
to carry firearms. As a general rule (which nonetheless has significant
exceptions), it has been possible for those who desired them to obtain
permits under discretionary systems in rural areas. The real impact of
shall-issue licensing systems thus occurs in the granting of permits to
the inhabitants of large cities and densely populated suburban counties.
Thus, shall-issue systems do "liberalize" the granting of
permits in metropolitan areas.
[34].
See 18 U.S.C. sec. 922(g).
[35].
See, for example, the licensing laws of Alaska, Arizona, Mississippi,
Nevada, Oklahoma, Oregon, Virginia, Washington, and Wyoming.
[36].
See, for example, the licensing laws of Alaska, Arkansas, Georgia,
Louisiana, Mississippi, Nevada, North Carolina, Oklahoma, Texas, Utah,
and Wyoming.
[37].
I do not speak here of whether, criminologically speaking, the presence
or absence of training requirements, or the differences in types of
training requirements, has any criminologically measurable effect on the
safety record of licensees. Here, I evaluate the requirements only from
the perspective of whether the purported purpose of training
requirements, to assure the public that those carrying firearms have
safe gun-handling skills, minimum proficiency, and knowledge of when
they may and may not shoot in self-defense, is clearly satisfied by an
analysis of the statutory requirements.
[38].
Some states require citizens to retreat, if possible, before using
lethal force in self-defense. That is essentially a refinement of the
concept of the "imminence" of the danger. If it is possible to
safely retreat and avoid using deadly force, the danger has not yet
become fully imminent.
39. See Sourcebook of Criminal
Justice Statistics (Washington: U.S. Department of Justice, 1992),
Table 3.10, "Estimated Percent Distribution of Personal and
Household Incidents," p. 264.
40. See ibid., Table 3.16,
"Estimated Percent Police Response Time for Personal and Household
Victimizations,"p. 271.
[41].
See the discussion of this point and legal authority cited by Cramer and
Kopel, pp. 730-31, where they recount some particularly egregious
examples of police failures to respond to pleas for help.
[42].
The principal thrust of this argument is to deny government the moral
authority to require someone to give up his ability to defend himself
when government does not agree to provide protection in return. That is,
it suggests that laws prohibiting citizens from using arms to defend
themselves are immoral because there is in fact no social contract. The
argument is, however, faulty to the extent that it suggests that, if
government did assume an obligation to protect each individual, it could
rightfully require its citizens to abandon their right to
self-protection. Social contract theorists like Hobbes and Locke held
the right to life to be irreducible and inalienable; government could
not require men to trade or abandon the right to defend themselves. As
Hobbes said, "A covenant not to defend myselfe from force, by
force, is alwayes voyd." See Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991),p. 98. The absurdity of
such a "trade" is apparent if one merely follows it through.
Suppose government did assume an obligation to protect me and then asked
me for my arms, so that I could not adequately defend myself. If
government then failed in its duty so that I was killed by a criminal,
the result would be that my estate would have a lawsuit for monetary
damages against the government. I would hardly believe that in trading
my life (i.e., my right to continue my life by defending it) for money
damages for my heirs I had made an equal exchange. The more radical
argument, based on the right to life, is that government has no right to
deprive its citizens of the means with which to defend themselves
regardless of whether or not it assumes an obligation to protect each
separate individual.
[43].
Lott and Mustard, p. 1.
[44].
Ibid., p. 65.
[45].
Robert Spitzer, The Politics of Gun Control (Chatham, N.J.:
Chatham House Publishing, 1995), pp. 181-97.
[46].
Lott and Mustard, p. 48.
[47].
The same problem would make it extremely difficult or impossible to
prove that shall-issue licensing laws increased violent crime. In
either case, the researcher requires a way to verify that more people
are in fact carrying guns postenactment.
[48].
Lott and Mustard, p. 7 n. 26.
[49].
My thanks to Daniel Polsby of the Northwestern University School of Law
for pointing this out to me.
[50].
Dan A. Black and Daniel S. Nagin, "Do 'Right to Carry' Laws Deter
Violent Crime?" Journal of Legal Studies 27 (forthcoming,
1998).
51. John R. Lott Jr., "The
Concealed Handgun Debate," unpublished paper, September 17, 1997, p.
15.
52. Ibid., p. 9.
53. Ibid.
54. Ibid., p. 12.
55. A fairly detailed account of
judicial interpretations of the Second Amendment and state
constitutional guarantees of the right to keep and bear arms can be
found in Cramer,pp. 221-67.
[56].
See, for example, Spitzer, pp. 25-48.
[57].
For a careful examination of the implications of adopting a
"states' rights" view of the Second Amendment, and explication
of the restrictions on federal gun control that might nevertheless
follow from the "states' rights" interpretation, see Glenn
Harlan Reynolds and Don B. Kates, "The Second Amendment and States'
Rights: A Thought Experiment," William and Mary Law Review
36 (1995): 1737.
58. See, for example, Don B.
Kates, "Handgun Prohibition and the Original Meaning of the Second
Amendment," p. 204; Sanford Levinson, "The Embarrassing Second
Amendment," Yale Law Journal 99 (1989): 637; William Van
Alstyne, "The Second Amendment and the Personal Right to
Arms," Duke Law Journal 43 (1994): 1236. A collection of
citations to other recent articles on the Second Amendment can be found
in Glenn Harlan Reynolds, "A Critical Guide to the Second
Amendment," Tennessee Law Review 62 (1995): 465 n. 18.
[59].
See Joyce Lee Malcolm, To Keep and Bear Arms--The Origins of an
Anglo-American Right (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press,
1994), pp. 162-63.
[60].
See Don B. Kates, "The Second Amendment: A Dialogue," Law
and Contemporary Problems 49 (1986): 143; Cramer,pp. 122-31.
[61].
Dred Scott v. Sanford, 60 U.S. 393, 417 (1857).
[62].
Ibid.
[63].
14 Stat. 176-177 (1866).
[64].
Cong. Globe, 39th Cong., 1st sess., 2764-65 (1866).
65. The author is aware of no
study indicating the frequency with which permit holders generally carry
their weapons.
66. The licensing statute
requires the issuance of a permit within 90 days, regardless of whether
the background check is finished at that time. Thus, some permits are
issued only to be revoked when the background search results are
received.
67. Cramer and Kopel, p. 692.
68. Ibid., pp. 692-93.
69. See "Handgun Law's First
Year Belies Fears of 'Blood in the Streets,'" Texas Lawyer,
December 9, 1996, p. 2.
70. See "Traffic Argument in
Texas Raises Questions on New Freedom to Carry Guns," New York
Times, February 23, 1996, p. A1.
71. See "Handgun Law's First
Year Belies Fears of 'Blood in the Streets,'" Texas Lawyer,
December 9, 1996, p. 2.
[72].
See Arthur L. Kellerman and Donald T. Reay, "Protection or Peril?
An Analysis of Firearms-Related Deaths in the Home," New England
Journal of Medicine, June 12, 1986,pp. 1557-60, quoted in
"Carrying Concealed Weapons--Questions and Answers," Handgun
Control Inc., Washington, n.d., p. 3.
[73].
Gary Kleck and Marc Gertz, "Armed Resistance to Crime: The
Prevalence and Nature of Self-Defense with a Gun," Journal of
Criminal Law and Criminology 86 (1995): 173.
[74].
See Daniel D. Polsby, "Firearms Costs, Firearms Benefits and the
Limits of Knowledge," Journal of Law and Criminology 86
(1995): 211. The footnote to this claim reads as follows: "Chicago
Police Department reports show that the percentage of Chicago homicide
victims with police records has been as high as 65% in recent individual
years. . . . In the early 1970s, the corresponding figures were
40%-45%."
[75].
"Carrying Concealed Weapons," p. 4. The FBI study cited is
"A Study of Selected Felonious Killings of Law Enforcement
Officers," September 1992.
76. 60 Minutes, October 1,
1995, transcript, p. 1.
[77].
Lott and Mustard, p. 3 n. 8.
[78].
Ibid.
[79].
See Kleck and Gertz, p. 173.
80. My thanks to Preston Covey of
Carnegie Mellon University for pointing this out to me.
81. Quoted in "Handgun Law's
First Year Belies Fears of 'Blood in the Streets,'" p. 2.
[82].
See "Carrying Concealed Weapons," p. 3. The numbers are drawn
from the U.S. Department of Justice, Bureau of Justice Statistics,
"Guns and Crime: Handgun Victimization, Firearm Self-Defense, and
Firearm Theft," April, 1994 (reporting that about 62,200 victims of
violent crime used guns to defend themselves) and from an analysis of
the National Crime Victimization Survey for data between 1987 and 1990
by University of Maryland researchers, David McDowall and Brian Wiersema,
"The Incidence of Civilian Defensive Firearms Use," December,
1994 (reporting about 65,000 such incidents a year). A 1991 study by
Phillip Cook of Duke University estimated the number of defensive uses a
year at 80,000 for the period 1979-87.
[83].
See Kleck and Gertz; and the 1994 National Survey of Private Ownership
of Firearms in the United States, conducted for the Police Foundation
under the sponsorship of the National Institute of Justice and discussed
in Phillip J. Cook and Jens Ludwig "You Got Me: How Many Defensive
Gun Uses Per Year?" Paper presented at the meeting of the American
Society of Criminology, Chicago, November 20, 1996.
[84].
See ibid.
[85].
See Kleck and Gertz, pp. 151-52.
[86].
Don B. Kates et al., "Guns and Public Health: Epidemic of Violence
or Pandemic of Propaganda?" Tennessee Law Review 62 (1995):
572-73.
[87].
The numbers, except for suicides, are given by Cook and Ludwig. The
number of gun crimes a year is contested. The figures are based on
National Crime Victimization Survey information, which counts as a gun
crime any crime in which the criminal had a firearm, even if the firearm
was not used by the criminal. Since criminal gun possession is included,
the number should not be taken as a count of total crimes of actual gun
misuse. See the discussion of this point in Kleck and Gertz, at 169.
[88].
The number of defensive gun uses is not necessarily a perfect proxy for
the social benefits of firearm ownership and use. On the one hand, the
mere fact that someone claims to have used his firearm defensively does
not, of course, mean that he did so justifiably in the eyes of the law.
If we add the qualification that the use has to be adjudged lawful as
well, (1) we are likely to be unable to determine how many such uses
there are, due to the amount and quality of information required to make
this determination, and (2) the number of "legitimate"
defensive uses, so defined, will likely decline. On the other hand, the
total positive value of firearms use would have to include the deterrent
value of widespread ownership (i.e., the number of crimes that simply do
not occur because of fear that victims or householders are armed). While
there is evidence that strongly suggests that criminals avoid those who
they believe are armed, there is no way to count the crimes that do not
occur because of firearm ownership. The number of defensive gun uses
thus appears to be one of the, admittedly imperfect, proxies for
societal benefits.
[89].
See Kleck and Gertz; and the 1994 National Survey of Private Ownership
of Firearms in the United States, conducted for the Police Foundation
under the sponsorship of the National Institute of Justice and discussed
in Cook and Ludwig.
[90].
Colin Loftin and Ellen J. MacKenzie, "Building National Estimates
of Violent Victimization," unpublished paper prepared for the
Symposium on the Understanding and Control of Violent Behavior, cited in
Kleck and Gertz, p. 155 n. 27.
[91].
Similarly, if it were argued that the number of defensive gun uses is
not a reasonable proxy for social benefit from gun use, the result would
also be that one has nothing to weigh against the costs, quantified in
terms of a body and injury count and number of gun crimes. Again, one
would not be able to assert either that the costs outweighed the
benefits or that the benefits outweighed the costs.
Published by the Cato Institute,
Policy Analysis is a regular series evaluating government policies and
offering proposals for reform. Nothing in Policy Analysis should be
construed as necessarily reflecting the views of the Cato Institute or
as an attempt to aid or hinder the passage of any bill before Congress.
Contact the Cato Institute for
reprint permission.Printed copies of Policy Analysis are $6.00 each
($3.00 each for five or more). To order, or for a complete listing of
available studies, write to: Cato Institute, 1000 Massachusetts Avenue
NW, Washington, DC, 20001. (202)842-0200 FAX (202)842-3490 E-mail [email protected]
| Hot
Topics | Policy
Analysis | Cato Home Page
| |